Case report / Étude de cas

Acting on a living will: a physician's dilemma

Michael Gordon, MD, FRCPC; Dan Levitt, MS

Canadian Medical Association Journal 1996; 155: 893-895

[résumé]


Dr. Gordon is vice-president of medical services and head of geriatrics and internal medicine, Baycrest Centre for Geriatric Care, North York, Ont., head of the Division of Geriatrics, Mount Sinai Hospital, professor of medicine, University of Toronto, and associate member, University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics, Toronto, Ont. Mr. Levitt is manager of residential services, British Columbia Association of Community Care, Vancouver, BC.

Paper reprints may be obtained from: Dr. Michael Gordon, Baycrest Centre for Geriatric Care, 3560 Bathurst St., North York ON M6A 2E1

© 1996 Canadian Medical Association (text and abstract/résumé)


Abstract

The implementation of a living will can give rise to ethical dilemmas for the patient's family and the health care professionals involved. The case reported here raises ques-tions about the right of patients to self-determination, the importance of quality-of-life considerations in treatment decisions and physicians' obligations with respect to the implementation of living wills. Physicians should ensure in advance that the instructions set out in a living will are unambiguous and should bring to the patient's attention any ethical difficulties that they foresee in carrying out those instructions.


Résumé

L'exécution d'un testament de vie peut poser des dilemmes éthiques aux membres de la famille du patient et aux professionnels de la santé en cause. Le cas décrit ici soulève des questions au sujet du droit à l'autodétermination des patients, de l'importance des considérations de qualité de vie dans les décisions de traitement et des obligations du médecin en ce qui a trait à l'exécution de testaments de vie. Les médecins doivent s'assurer à
l'avance que les instructions données dans un testament de vie sont claires et devraient signaler à leur patient toute difficulté sur le plan éthique que l'exécution de ces instructions pourrait selon eux poser.


Advances in medical technology, new legislation and increased public awareness have changed the framework in which health care practitioners make clinical decisions. Recent court rulings in the United States[1,2] and Canada[3,4] have made it clear that patients may refuse medical treatments and that physicians and other health care providers are obligated to abide by such decisions. However, despite the general acceptance of the patient's right to self-determination, practitioners can unduly influence the course of treatment unless they accept unequivocally the input and directives of the patient or a designated surrogate.

From a legal and professional perpective, upholding the patient's right to self-determination in medical care is relatively straightforward. Physicians and other health care providers should welcome the patient's participation in decision making and, when appropriate, accept the involvement of a substitute decision-maker or comply with the patient's wishes as expressed in an advance directive. In actual practice, however, problems of clinical and ethical judgement can arise. Those involved may not agree that the directive applies to the situation at hand or may feel that acting upon it would be illegal, immoral or contrary to professional ethics. The case reported here raises issues that must be resolved in order to achieve an outcome acceptable to a patient, his or her family and the professional caregivers involved.

Case report

A 72-year-old man had been a patient in a chronic care facility for many years because of nondementing progressive neurologic paralysis in all limbs and, ultimately, the diaphragm. For most of his years in hospital he had been mentally capable and socially active. All who knew him were impressed by his courage, determination, humour and zest for life.

Although the patient received attentive care, his clinical condition gradually deteriorated. He required diaphragmatic pacemakers to assist respiration and, later, a respirator to supplement and, ultimately, sustain his breathing. He needed total nursing care but was able to eat and communicate adequately until very late in his illness. Four years previously he had stated in writing that he did not wish to be maintained alive if he were a "vegetable" or required "permanent artificial feeding." His only living relative and designated substitute decision-maker lived in another city.

Over the next few months the patient experienced recurrent lung, urinary tract and skin infections, poorly controlled seizures and variable but often diminished levels of consciousness. The issue of the living will was raised by his relative. Although the patient required nasogastric feeding and his mental function was vastly diminished, the attending physician and other professional staff were unsure whether his directive clearly applied. They sought to clarify what the patient had meant by the word "vegetable." A comprehensive assessment of competence was made to determine whether, during his state of best wakefulness, the patient could competently clarify, confirm or redirect his plan of treatment. The assessors believed that he could not and that the existing instructions, although vague, provided the only directive obtainable and would have to be interpreted.

The attending physician and other members of the health care team were emotionally and morally uncomfortable in complying with the implied instruction to stop life-sustaining treatment. The patient's relative vacillated and hoped that the clinical ethics committee of the hospital would help resolve the issue.

The committee agreed to help clarify the issues within an ethical and legal framework. After deliberating with the committee the physician and team agreed that the living will was valid and relevant to the current situation. However, some of the team members, especially the physician, were reluctant to stop the respirator in accordance with the living will. They agreed to remove the nasogastric feeding tube and to withhold antibiotic or other therapy in the event of acute illness. The patient succumbed to an infection soon afterward.

Comments

A key difficulty in this case lay in determining whether the patient's living will applied to his clinical situation: that is, whether his condition was that of a "vegetable," the term used in his living will, such that mechanical respiration should be stopped. The patient's history of accepting great challenges was interpreted by the physician and others as an indication that he would not want to give up whatever life he had at that time.[5] Unfortunately, the patient had not discussed such issues explicitly with his physician or relative and had not been asked to define the word "vegetable." In the absence of such clarification, the "reasonable person's" definition of being a "vegetable" could be accepted. The patient's clinical condition probably met the criteria for such a state.[6,7]

Normally the substitute decision-maker and the members of the health care team would be expected to comply with a patient's advance directive unless there was compelling reason to the contrary.[8] The substitute decision-maker would be required to request that any treatments that maintained the patient in a vegetative state be withheld. According to legislation such as Ontario's Substitute Decisions Act (1995), the failure of the substitute decision-maker to comply with the patient's advance directive can be challenged by the attending physician through the office of the Public Guardian and Trustee.[9]

Physicians who accept the principle of patient autonomy and the validity of advance directives are able to follow the instructions of a living will without personal conflict, even when this requires them to stop life-maintaining respiratory support.[10] The main issue in this case was the physician's view that it would be wrong to personally and directly cause the death of a patient.[11] This was complicated by the will's vagueness, the patient's inability to clarify his position and his relative's reluctance to take a stand.

This apparent conflict between the rights of the patient and the values of the attending physician must be examined. A living will is an instrument of a patient's autonomy. When the patient is able to express his or her wishes actively, it is more difficult for a physician to refuse them. A living will is static, however, and some physicians may not consider it to be as authoritative as personal discussions.[12]

How should physicians respond when their ethical or moral principles conflict with the patient's expressed wishes? Codes of ethics such as those of the CMA and the American Medical Association[13,14] state that physicians are not required to carry out instructions that conflict with their own ethical principles. If a physician cannot comply with a patient's wishes he or she is obliged to find another physician to take over the case. But what are the attending physician's obligations if there is no other physician willing to carry out the patient's legally binding directives? One could argue that if the patient's request is legal and consistent with the standard of care established in the jurisdiction, then the physician's objections must be set aside in favour of the patient's wishes.

The ethical and legal basis for patient autonomy is clear. The case for physician autonomy is less compelling, although it does have some basis in tradition, practice and religious belief. In the case reported here, once the physician decided that it was not possible personally to carry out the patient's directive the voluntary transfer of care to another physician was agreed to as a back-up. To avoid such circumstances, physicians should, if possible, inform their patients at the time a living will is drawn up of any difficulties they foresee in carrying out its instructions.[15]

The nonmedical members of the team who felt uncomfortable in complying with the living will were caught in the same quandary. Should nurses and other health care providers have the option of transferring care to other caregivers in the event of a moral or ethical conflict? In particular cases it may be possible to accommodate a nurse's strong ethical or religious beliefs by having another nurse carry out directions, but this is not necessarily translated into institutional or professional policy. In general, the implications for care of such an option would be unacceptable, and professional standards do not appear to allow nurses to ignore the legally acceptable wishes of patients under their care, whether expressed orally or in writing. If the withdrawal of treatment results in the termination of breathing and other physiologic activities, nurses are expected to provide the best level of care to assure comfort and to avoid unnecessary suffering even if they do not agree with the patient's decision.

Although most physicians support conceptually the use of advance directives,[16] they are not always comfortable with their implementation, especially when the withdrawal rather than noninitiation of treatment is required. Such conflict could potentially lead to situations in which patients are not offered the option of trying a therapy which, if not successful, would be withdrawn.[17] A trial of an intervention such as tube feeding or dialysis is attractive to many practitioners because it allows observation of the effect of potentially beneficial therapies without commitment to permanent therapy that may not achieve the desired goal. The difference between not initiating therapy and withdrawing unsuccessful therapy is perhaps illusory, although these two approaches often prompt different emotional responses on the part of care providers.[18,19]

The ultimate professional and moral obligation of physicians whose religious or ethical principles conflict with the expressed wishes of a patient can be examined only within socially and professionally acceptable standards of medicine.[20,21] A patient cannot expect a physician to carry out a request for treatment for which there is no reliable evidence of benefit.[22] Conversely, a competent patient may decline a highly effective available treatment even though the physician strenuously disagrees with this decision, and the physician must, ethically and legally, comply with that wish.[23]

The withdrawal or noninitiation of potentially life-saving treatment is perceived by some physicians as tantamount to euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide. However, in such situations no deliberate action is taken by the physician to end life; therefore, contemporary ethical and legal opinion is that the patient has a right to expect such nondirect action on the part of the physician in accordance with an advance directive.[24] In contrast, proposed physician-assisted suicide legislation in most jurisdictions does allow physicians to choose not to comply with the patient's request.[25]

When ethical conflicts arise physicians have the option of transferring their responsibility to another practitioner. However, this does not address the moral issue of the physician's ultimate obligation and responsibility.[26] If such a transfer is not feasible is it the responsibility of the physician always to comply with the patient's wishes?[27] Strong arguments support the principle that the patient's wishes take precedence over the physician's personal views.[28] This is the essence of medicine as a "serving profession." The patient must never be abandoned by a physician,[29] even at the expense of the physician's personal code, unless honouring the patient's request would result in the certain death of the physician (such as by giving mouth-to-mouth resuscitation for a patient with a lethal communicable disease). A physician's discomfort in living with the consequences of a medical act that favours a patient's bona fide and legal rights over the physician's personal moral or religious principles does not appear to be an excessive price to pay for patients to feel confident that their reasonable wishes will have meaning at the end of their life.

I thank Dr. Peter A. Singer, director of the University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics, and Ms. Gilda Berger, who, at the time of writing, was an articling student at the Willowdale Community Legal Services, for their assistance in the preparation of the manuscript.

References

  1. In re Karen Quinlan 70 NJ 10, 355 A 2d 647 (1976).
  2. Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health, 110 S Ct 2841 (1990).
  3. Malette v. Shulman (1990) 72 OR (2d) 417 (Ont CA).
  4. Sue Rodriguez v. British Columbia (Attorney General) (1993) 3 SCR 519.
  5. Emanuel EJ, Emanuel LL, Stoeckle JD, et al. Advance directives: stability of patients' treatment choices. Arch Intern Med 1994; 154: 209-17.
  6. Jennet B, Plum F. Persistent vegetative state after brain damage: a syndrome in search of a name. Lancet 1972; 1: 734-7.
  7. Multi-Society Task Force on PVS. Medical aspects of the persistent vegetative state. N Engl J Med 1994; 330: 1499-508.
  8. Schneiderman LJ, Pearlman RA, Kaplan RM, Anderson JP, Rosenberg EM. Relationship of general advance directive instructions to specific life-sustaining treatment preferences in patients with serious illness. Arch Intern Med 1992; 152: 2114-22.
  9. Substitute Decisions Act, SO 1995 c 30.
  10. Schneiderman LJ, Teetzel H. Who decides who decides? When disagreement occurs between the physician and the patient's appointed proxy about the patient's decision-making capacity. Arch Intern Med 1995; 155: 793-6.
  11. Davidson KW, Hackler C, Caradine DR, et al. Physicians' attitudes on advance directives. JAMA 1989; 262: 2415-9.
  12. Fried TR, Gillick MR. Medical decision-making in the last six months of life: choices about limitation of care. J Am Geriatr Soc 1994; 42: 303-7.
  13. Canadian Medical Association. Code of Ethics. The Association, Ottawa, 1990.
  14. American Medical Association. Code of Ethics: Current Opinions with Annotations. The Association, Chicago, 1994.
  15. Danis M, Southerland LI, Garrett JM, et al. A prospective study of advance directives for life-sustaining care. N Engl J Med 1991; 324: 882-8.
  16. Hughes DL, Singer PA. Family physicians' attitudes toward advance directives. CMAJ 1992; 146: 1937-44.
  17. Reilly RB, Teasdale TA, McCullough LB. Projecting patients' preferences from living wills: an invalid strategy for measurement of dementia with life-threatening illness. J Am Geriatr Soc 1994; 42: 997-1003.
  18. Jecker NS, Emanuel L. Are acting and omitting morally equivalent? A reappraisal. J Am Geriatr Soc 1995; 43: 696-701.
  19. Brody H. Withdrawing versus withholding therapy: still a pernicious distinction. J Am Geriatr Soc 1995; 43: 716-7.
  20. Ellard J. Medical ethics: Fact or fiction? Med J Aust 1993; 158: 460-4.
  21. Weir RF, Gostin L. Decisions to abate life-sustaining treatment for nonautonomous patients: ethical standards and legal liability for physicians after Cruzan. JAMA 1990; 264: 1846-53.
  22. Wazner SH, Federman DD, Adelstein SJ, et al. The physician's responsibility toward hopelessly ill patients: a second look. N Engl J Med 1990; 320: 844-9.
  23. Silberfeld M, Madigan KV, Dickens BM. Liability concerns about the implementation of advance directives. CMAJ 1994; 151: 285-9.
  24. Korgaonkar G, Tribe D. Doctors, living wills and the law. Br J Hosp Med 1993; 49: 576-81.
  25. American Association of Retired Persons. Survey of State Laws 1994: Advance Directives. The Association, Washington, 1994.
  26. Edwards MJ, Tolle SW. Disconnecting the ventilator at the request of a patient who knows he will then die: the doctor's anguish. Ann Intern Med 1992; 117: 254-6.
  27. Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association. Decisions near the end of life. JAMA 1992; 267: 2229-33
  28. Pellegrino ED: Nonabandonment: an old obligation revisited. Ann Intern Med 1995; 122: 377-8.
  29. Quill TE, Cassel CK: Nonabandonment: a central obligation for physicians. Ann Intern Med 1995; 122: 368-74.

| CMAJ October 1, 1996 (vol 155, no 7)  /  JAMC le 1er octobre 1996 (vol 155, no 7) |