A Manifesto for Gender Responsibility and Equality in Every-Day Life
1) My proposal represents a functional aspect of
ethical constructivism, an epistemological school of thought (see, for
example, <http://www.univie.ac.at/cognition/constructivism>)
and it serves the following purposes: 1) to postulate some pragmatic aspects
of my intellectual/personal position toward feminisms; 2) to present my
approach to men in scholarship and the academe; and 3) to satisfy my commitment
to oppose negative discrimination in all walks of life actively, thus responding
to the implicit demands of ethical constructivism. The desired readership
of my argument is, in the first instance, the heterosexual male majority
in academia but many of the suggestions here proposed apply to all men
(and women) in all walks of life. Although the term "negative discrimination"
is cumbersome, I am using it here because discrimination per se
is not necessarily negative. I am differentiating between discrimination
as an "objective" point of view, in the present context void of value judgements,
and "negative discrimination," which results in such as apartheid, the
objectification and suppression of women, racial hatred, etc.
2) Elaine Showalter writes: "I believe that the
fundamental changes have now begun that make the formation of a strong
critical community around the issue of gender a genuine and exciting possibility.
While this community ... will include critics who are male and female,
black and white, gay, lesbian, and straight, its members can explore a
range of gendered subjectivities and literatures besides their own. Like
other aspects of literary analysis, talking about gender without a commitment
to dismantling sexism, racism, and homophobia, can degenerate into nothing
more than a talk show, with men trying to monopolize the (post)feminist
conversation. But ... the genuine addition of gender as a 'central problem
in every text' read and taught, 'whatever the era and whoever the author,'
could also move us a step further towards post-patriarchy. That's a step
worth trying to take together" ("The Rise of Gender." Speaking of Gender.
Ed. Elaine Showalter. New York: Routledge, 1989. 1-13. Page 2).
3) The implementation of Showalter's perspective
in the domain of higher learning is critical because male academics comprise
the majority in our institutions of higher learning and because they constitute
intellectual leadership. Their education is an indispensable step in the
struggle against gender negative discrimination in our society. This education
should occur in two related areas: 1) by the re-structuring of cultural
codes, customs, habits, perceptions, laws, etc., and, most importantly,
2) male academics ought to "coordinate" aspects of their personal lives,
their scholarship, and their academic activities. In other words, the domains
of the personal, the intellectual, and the professional should interact
in a harmonious display resulting in an environment of non-negative-discrimination
between men and women. This is what I term "gender responsibility" as part
of a general environment of social responsibility.
4) Patriarchy and its values are mainly social in
origin and even if we take into account biological, physiological, or neurological
differences, these should -- and must -- be restructured towards equity
in all walks of life, based on the tenets of ethical Constructivism. The
proposition that women are unable to perform certain tasks because they
are female, is untenable. If they are now handicapped in certain endeavours,
they are so because of entrenched oppression, may that be obvious or implicit
in designations of roles for women. This can and must be changed. Society
must find avenues and must accommodate women so that gender will be no
more a base for negative discrimination.
5) My postulate is that gender responsibility is
one of the most important social (intellectual, psychological, institutional,
legal, etc.) tasks of our time (this was said by some feminists already
in the nineteenth century), involving almost all areas of interaction and
communication. It is so, because it will become possible to eradicate negative
discrimination -- racial, religious, ethnic, sexual, etc., -- only after
gender responsibility has become an unquestioned and unquestionable universal
human quality. What is closest to the body, has to be resolved first, so
to speak. This does not mean that the advocation and fight against racial
discrimination, for example, is not as important as gender responsibility
or that it should not be combatted side by side with gender negative discrimination.
Rather, I propose that because we all encounter gender codes and behaviour
first (i.e., from birth in the family environment), gender negative discrimination
is the most pervasive and unchallenged situation we grow up with. One cannot,
it seems to me, hope to eliminate racism and other negative discriminations
before we eliminate gender negative discrimination and its mechanisms.
More, this is a necessary task in all cultures. Negative discrimination
against women and the feminine, is, at present, a characteristic of almost
all cultures, although so to various degrees and intensities. Therefore,
gender responsibility -- because it transcends cultural, social, economic,
etc., demarcations and because human interaction is most immediately marked
by gender relationships -- attains ultimate importance. Further, if gender
responsibility evolves into an universal human characteristic, other negative
discriminations will either logically disappear (an admittedly idealistic
view) or at least they will be easier to combat. In the following, I would
like to offer a functional and operational framework of gender responsibility:
5.1 A point of departure is that as male academics,
it is of crucial importance that we are aware of gender responsibility.
This awareness means position-taking, i.e., the rethinking of our beliefs,
attitudes, etc., and extends into discussions in academic circles and at
home. Generally, it means the channeling of areas of our private life into
gender responsibility and vice versa.
5.2 One of the elements of gender responsibility
begins with and acts within language. Linguistic awareness at work and
in our work, at home, in partnership, and with children, is a crucial part
of gender responsibility.
5.3 The attraction to a woman: Subsequent actions
to translate this into a relationship is still largely placed onto the
male by social conditioning. It is one's gender responsibility to reduce
this socially conditioned demand and to accept or to solicit the "equalizing"
involvement of your partner.
5.4 As a polite and courteous individuals we should
behave accordingly towards women -- but not according to codes of "gentlemanlike"
behaviour, i.e., we are polite and courteous towards women not because
they are women but because we are polite and courteous individuals.
5.5 In situations of "men only" conversations or
"out
with the boys," we should attempt to take a position which will ultimately
result in gender responsibility, at least in our presence.
5.6 In general terms, we should watch ourselves
and our attitudes: Always realize when gender responsibility is absent,
to whatever degree, from our thinking, emotions, and social interaction.
5.7 It should be kept in mind that our sexual behaviour
with a partner or spouse manifests our awareness and understanding of gender
responsibility.
5.8 If in a long-term relationship: Whether your
partner/spouse is at home or whether she is working, housework must be
shared. If you have the misfortune of having grown up without acquiring
skills such as cooking, doing laundry, etc., you should learn them. Also,
it is important that we do the less "fun-type" housework, too. We should
not chose gardening, because we like gardening, and dislike cooking and
then claim that we share housework. In a situation where by consensus it
has been agreed upon that your spouse stays at home, for example, to raise
children, the principles here postulated should still apply. The principles
of gender responsibility become even more important when your spouse has
a career on her own. Her career and its demands should be integral to your
gender responsibility. The demands of both careers and the sharing of household
tasks should be frequently discussed and mediated.
5.9 If there are children: Gender responsibility
requires our involvement beyond that of a
paterfamilias. It begins
with participation in pregnancy classes, continues with participation in
the birth (unless there is a medical reason why you cannot attend), continues
still during night time feedings, diaper changing, etc., and both parents
participate in the years of schooling, etc.
5.10 In the academic/bureaucratic sphere it is inappropriate,
for example that we address, for example, the departmental secretary (usually
a woman) by her first name while she addresses you by "Professor X" or
"Dr Y." We must either address each other by first names, or you her by
Ms, Mrs, or Miss X and she then you by Professor X or Dr Y. (This latter
point is a North American cultural and linguistic issue while in other
cultures -- continental Europe, Asia, etc. -- it is more often than not
not an issue).
5.11. We should read feminist and antisexist literature.
The extent of this will, of course, depend on our field, interest, and
available time. However, whatever our field, some knowledge of recent feminist
texts will help us to understand and clarify gender responsibility. More
importantly, we should read literature (primary texts) in general critically,
i.e., with awareness of gender responsibility. And scholars working in
the humanities should attempt to work promoting feminist criticism (regardless
of some feminists' objections to "appropriation."
5.12 If we subscribe to gender responsibility, our
opponent, in a context of dialogue, in society (and within ourselves) is
the male proponent of patriarchy and, as well, the female proponent of
patriarchy. In both cases, we should attempt to educate and to convince,
by word and deed.
5.13 Militant feminists, we must realize, as irritating
or even unfair they and their activities and concepts appear to be to us,
are (necessary) transgressions and aggressions. If we encounter suspicion
in our attempts to propagate gender responsibility, this must be disregarded
-- we should proceed with our task, but without forgetting to silence one's
inner male response, often a negative one.
5.14 Gender responsibility also means sensitivity
to (socially conditioned) codes of behaviour of women. For example, it
appears to me that when passing an obstruction in a building or on the
street at the same time when a woman does, the woman utters "excuse me"
more readily than the man, usually she is the first to apologize. This
is an example of women's behaviour towards obstruction (as a concept),
toward resistance. As male academics are the majority at institutions of
higher learning, it is important to recognize the difference in male/female
approaches in dealing with problems and problem solving, large and small.
5.15 An important and controversial issue is the
question of "reverse discrimination." We must have faith in academic integrity
and assume that qualified male academics are not negative-discriminated
against because of their gender. However, there are areas where reverse
discrimination, in a specific sense, is justified. The reality of the matter
is that the status quo of the majority of men is unacceptable because it
originates in the fact of the general negative discrimination against women.
If, in certain cases affirmative action means a preference for qualified
women candidates and leads to the elimination of men candidates, this is
a price to pay, that is, this is something we men ought to accept. It is
appropriate and justified to change from domination of male academics into
a gender parity by means of a preference for qualified women academics.
6) The addition here of an "autobiographical detail"
is consistent with the concept of gender responsibility and it also confirms
my postulate of the importance of an ethical constructivism. I must admit
-- hoping that this will not detract from the seriousness of my above stated
points of consideration -- that my own awareness of gender responsibility
has developed more easily than if I had had a more ordinary and traditional
life. At the same time, the contents of this Manifesto are based on realities
of my life, my own beliefs and actions and (re)actions. Now, in 2000, I
am fifty years old, have been married for twenty-four years, and we have
two children. My sensitivity to negative discrimination developed early:
I repeatedly experienced negative discrimination (social, cultural, bureaucratic,
etc.) in my country of birth and as a refugee/foreigner in several other
countries. In addition, I have seen this negative discrimination in continuous
action in the life of my mother, single since I was fourteen years old.
Thus, I have come to regard social responsibility and within that, gender
responsibility an integral part of my individuality. The continuous integration
of gender responsibility into my individual make-up has been aided by my
spouse, who earned a doctorate in a medical science and who successfully
combined the pleasures and responsibilities of marriage, her career, and
our children. She and I share and enact the principles here proposed.
7) I am aware and admit readily that a "manifesto"
for gender responsibility/equality in every-day life may be a curious approach
and it may even appear ridiculous to some. At the same time, I believe
that the specific form of the "manifesto" represents an advantageous way
of trying to transmit my approach to the questions about and problematics
of gender today. I should also like to point out that my approach is to
be understood in the context of Western culture and society.
Note: The text of the Manifesto has appeared previously in earlier variations: 1) "In 1991: A Manifesto of Gender Responsibility." Men's Studies Review: A Quarterly Publication of the Men's Studies Association (Harriman, TN) 8.3 (1991): 16-18. and 2) in Comparative Literature: Theory, Method, Application. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1998. 173-77.