Anthropomorphism – the ascription to animals of human
psychological qualities – is presently undergoing something of a
revival. Several thoughtful commentators have suggested that, while it
cannot be good science to view members of different species as just like
us (what Frans de Waal, 2002, colorfully labelled "Bambification"), some
other forms of anthropomorphism can be constructive and helpful to
comparative psychologists. These proposals include Gordon Burghardt’s
"critical anthropomorphism" (1991), Marc Bekoff’s "biocentric
anthropomorphism" (2000) and Frans de Waal’s "animal-centered
anthropomorphism" (1997). Though there are differences between these
approaches, they share the belief that projecting oneself into the
situation of a member of another species can lead to the production of
useful hypotheses for further scientific study.
I shall argue that anthropomorphism, even of the
reformed varieties, should have no place in an objective science of
comparative psychology. Fundamentally this is because anthropomorphism
is a form of mentalism, and as such is not amenable to objective study.
Labelling animal behaviors with everyday terms from lay psychology does
not explain anything. Rather it is an example of the nominalist fallacy
– the belief that naming something explains it (Blumberg & Wasserman,
1995). To see how we got to the present situation it is useful to start
with a little history.
A Brief History of Anthropomorphism
Figure 1. Charles Darwin as photographed
by Julia Margaret Cameron on the Isle of Wight on a return visit
in 1868. This copy was given to Darwin by Samuel H. Scudder.
Scudder was an American admirer of Darwin’s, and one of the
early editors of Science magazine. Underneath this print Darwin
wrote, "I like this Photograph very much better than any other
which has been taken of me. Ch. Darwin." Copyright © 1999 The
American Photography Museum, Inc. All Rights Reserved. Obtained
with permission.
|
|
Back in the bad old days BD (Before Darwin) the
relationship of humans to the rest of creation was quite
straightforward. Animals were brutes and people were special. Humans had
been generated in a separate act of creation. Where animals made do with
instinct and habit, we were blessed with rationality and language – two
things that placed us closer to the angels and lifted us above the rest
of the earth’s creatures. Descartes had argued that animals were
machines, complicated machines, but machines nonetheless. They were
governed by the same laws as inanimate matter. Human bodies had a
machine-like aspect to them, but they also possessed a god-given
immortal soul which gave them rationality – what we would today call
intelligence and consciousness.
After Darwin (AD) this idea of a hard and fast line
between humans and other species became untenable. In the first
published statement of his theory of evolution by natural selection,
On The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection or the
Preservation of Favored Races in the Struggle for Life, finally
published after nearly two decades of procrastination in 1859, Darwin
avoided saying much about humans. On the last page he noted simply,
"Light will be thrown on the origin of man and his history" (p. 488).
The co-discoverer of the theory of natural selection, Alfred Russel
Wallace, did not accept that evolution could have any relevance to human
psychology (Wallace, 1869). Darwin, however, disagreed and in 1871
published a major work setting out the similarities between human and
animal minds: The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex.
In that volume, Darwin pointed out that there was "no fundamental
difference between man and the higher mammals in their mental
faculties," though he was also careful to note on the same page that the
"difference in mental power between the highest ape and the lowest
savage" is "immense" (Darwin, 1871, p. 45).
|
Figure 2. George Henry Lewes, originator
of the application of the term ‘anthropomorphism’ to animals.
Image from Wikipedia in public domain. |
For centuries, "anthropomorphism" had referred to the
ascription to angels and God of human qualities (‘anthros’ – man;
‘morphos’ – form). This commonplace of medieval theology was banned by
Bishop Etienne Tempier’s Condemnations of 1277 (Daston, 2005). According
to the Oxford English Dictionary (2006), it was George Herbert Lewes who
was the first to extend the usage of this word to animals, in a work
first published in 1858, the year in which Darwin’s revolutionary
evolutionary ideas became public through a presentation at the Linnean
Society. Lewes, a Victorian polymath, wrote in his Sea-side Studies
at Ilfracombe, Tenby, the Scilly Isles, and Jersey that, in
considering the vision of mollusks (which, he believed, had only
rudimentary sensitivity to light), "We speak with large latitude of
anthropomorphism when we speak of the ‘vision’ of these animals…
Molluscan vision is not human vision; nor in accurate language is it
vision at all…" (1860, p. 359). He went on, "…we are incessantly at
fault in our tendency to anthropomorphise, a tendency which causes us to
interpret the actions of animals according to the analogies of human
nature" (1860, p. 385).
Darwin’s own approach to animals, in the Descent
and also in The Expression of Emotions in Man and Animals (1872),
was quite clearly anthropomorphic in intent (though, now that all of
Darwin’s published works have been digitized, it is possible to state
definitively that he never used the term himself,
http://darwin-online.org.uk/). Darwin was out to prove that humans and
animals shared many psychological qualities. He argued that one could
observe in man, "the same senses as the lower animals," consequently,
"his fundamental intuitions must be the same." He went on, "Man has also
some few instincts in common [with other species, such] as that of
self-preservation, sexual love, the love of the mother for her new-born
offspring, the desire possessed by the latter to suck, and so forth"
(Darwin, 1871, p. 66). Other aspects of psychology struck Darwin as
being shared between humans and other species too: "the lower animals,
like man, manifestly feel pleasure and pain, happiness and misery"
(1871, p. 69). Darwin admitted only that "man…is capable of incomparably
greater and more rapid improvement than is any other animal…; and this
is mainly due to his power of speaking and handing down his acquired
knowledge" (1871, p. 79).
It is worth quoting Darwin’s view on the similarities
in psychology between humans and animals at some length:
|
Figure 3. "The same [dog as in previous
picture] in a humble and affectionate frame of mind." The
Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. Charles Darwin
(1882, p. 53, Figure 6). Reproduced with permission from The
Complete Work of Charles Darwin Online (http://darwin-online.org.uk/) |
It has, I think, now been shewn that man and the
higher animals, especially the Primates, have some few instincts in
common. All have the same senses, intuitions, and
sensations,—similar passions, affections, and emotions, even the
more complex ones, such as jealousy, suspicion, emulation,
gratitude, and magnanimity; they practice deceit and are revengeful;
they are sometimes susceptible to ridicule, and even have a sense of
humour; they feel wonder and curiosity; they possess the same
faculties of imitation, attention, deliberation, choice, memory,
imagination, the association of ideas, and reason, though in very
different degrees. The individuals of the same species graduate in
intellect from absolute imbecility to high excellence. They are also
liable to insanity, though far less often than in the case of man.
Nevertheless, many authors have insisted that man is divided by an
insuperable barrier from all the lower animals in his mental
faculties. I formerly made a collection of above a score of such
aphorisms, but they are almost worthless, as their wide difference
and number prove the difficulty, if not the impossibility, of the
attempt. It has been asserted that man alone is capable of
progressive improvement; that he alone makes use of tools or fire,
domesticates other animals, or possesses property; that no animal
has the power of abstraction, or of forming general concepts, is
self-conscious and comprehends itself; that no animal employs
language; that man alone has a sense of beauty, is liable to
caprice, has the feeling of gratitude mystery, etc.; believes in
God, or is endowed with a conscience (1871, p. 79).
|
Figure 4. Shanklin Chine, Isle of Wight
from "Brannon’s Picture of The Isle of Wight" (Brannon, G.
1849). Darwin started the Origin of Species here in 1858. He
wrote to his friend, J. D. Hooker, "we think this the nicest
sea-side place, which we have ever seen." The present author
spent most of his childhood in Shanklin. Reproduced pursuent to
the Project Gutenberg™ license. |
Darwin went on to argue that at least incipient hints
of all of these qualities could be observed in nonhuman species.
Language is suggested in the communicative noises of animals. Even
belief in god is prefigured "in the deep love of a dog for his master,
associated with complete submission, some fear, and perhaps other
feelings" (1871, p. 96).
Since Darwin was not a professor, he had no students
in the ordinary sense (Browne, 2003). He did, however, encourage some
younger followers. His key successor in the realm of animal intelligence
was George Romanes. Romanes has often been ridiculed for writing of
human qualities in a wide range of animal species. It is only fair,
however, to point out that Romanes was continuing in a manner that was
clearly laid out for him by Darwin.
Romanes had a very different position on the value of
anthropomorphism from Lewes. In his major text, Animal Intelligence
(1883), Romanes started out by arguing from the premise that "the
external indications of mental processes which we observe in animals are
trustworthy, so …we are justified in inferring particular mental states
from particular bodily actions." He continued, "It follows that in
consistency we must everywhere apply the same criteria. For instance, if
we find a dog or a monkey exhibiting marked expressions of affection,
sympathy, jealousy, rage, etc., few persons are sceptical enough to
doubt that the complete analogy which these expressions afford with
those which are manifested by man, sufficiently prove the existence of
mental states analogous to those in man of which these expressions are
the outward and visible signs" (1883, p. 8-9). Romanes recognized that
some people might be hesitant to follow these analogies through to
animals very different from ourselves, like bees and ants, but he
concludes:
|
Figure 5. George John Romanes, early
defender of animal anthropomoprhism. Frontispiece to The Life
and Letters of George John Romanes by Ethel D. Romanes & George
J. Romanes (1896). Longmans, Green. London. Image from Wikipedia
in public domain.
|
|
Figure 6. Conwy Lloyd Morgan, early critic of animal
anthropomorphism. Image copyright the University of Bristol.
Reproduced with permission. |
If we observe an ant or a bee apparently
exhibiting sympathy or rage, we must either conclude that some
psychological state resembling that of sympathy or rage is present,
or else refuse to think about the subject at all; from the
observable facts there is no other inference open. Therefore, having
full regard to the progressive weakening of the analogy from human
to brute psychology as we recede through the animal kingdom
downwards from man, still, as it is the only analogy available, I
shall follow it throughout the animal series (1883, p. 9).
Romanes does seem a little discomforted by the point
to which his reasoning has brought him. He admits that as we "get down
as low as insects" there is clearly a "progressive weakening of the
analogy" of human to animal minds, but he nonetheless, "confidently assert[s] …that the known facts of human psychology furnish the best
available pattern of the probable facts of insect psychology." He
summarizes his approach thus:
Just as the theologians tell us—and logically
enough— that if there is a Divine Mind, the best, and indeed only,
conception we can form of it is that which is formed on the analogy,
however imperfect, supplied by the human mind; so with ‘inverted
anthropomorphism’ we must apply a similar consideration with a
similar conclusion to the animal mind. The mental states of an
insect may be widely different from those of a man, and yet most
probably the nearest conception that we can form of their true
nature is that which we form by assimilating them to the pattern of
the only mental states with which we are actually acquainted. And
this consideration, it is needless to point out, has a special
validity to the evolutionist, inasmuch as upon his theory there must
be a no less than a physiological, continuity a psychological,
extending throughout the length and breadth of the animal kingdom
(1883, p. 9-10).
From my reading of Darwin, I would argue that there
is not much in Romanes’s Animal Intelligence with which Darwin
(who had died the year before, in 1882) would have disagreed. Romanes
describes how he had considered restricting himself only to anecdotes
about animals that had been recorded by "observers well known as
competent." He decided not to follow this route because, "the most
remarkable instances of the display of intelligence were recorded by
persons bearing names more or less unknown to fame" (1883, p. viii).
Consequently Romanes’s accounts of animal psychology tend to be
credulous. It is this gullibility, I believe, and not a general
philosophical distinction, which distinguishes Romanes’s writing on
animal psychology from Darwin’s -- though the difference is not great,
and at least one careful commentator has come to the exact opposite
conclusion and rated Darwin the more gullible collector (Boakes, 1984).
|
Figure 7. Lloyd Morgan’s dog Tony lifting
a gate latch with the back of his head. "…the lifting of the
latch was unquestionably hit on by accident, and the trick was
only rendered habitual by repeated association in the same
situation of the chance act and the happy escape. Once firmly
established, however, the behavior remained constant throughout
the remainder of the dog’s life, some five or six years. And, I
may add, I could not succeed, not withstanding much expenditure
of biscuits, in teaching him to lift the latch more elegantly
with his muzzle instead of the back of his head…" Morgan, C. L.
(1930). The Animal Mind. London, E. Arnold & Co.
Reproduced from
http://www.pigeon.psy.tufts.edu/psych26/morgan.htm with
permission of Robert Cook.
|
A decade after Romanes’s Animal Intelligence,
another British writer, Conwy Lloyd Morgan, in his Introduction to
Comparative Psychology (1894), published what has been perceived as
a critique of Romanes’s work. Skinner (1938) argued that Morgan was
trying to dispense with mental categories in the explanation of animal
behavior. It is true that Morgan, with his "basal principle" (or "canon"
as it has become known), was attempting to add some discipline to Romanes’s attempts to account for animal behavior. It is not accurate,
however, to ascribe to Morgan a desire to eschew mentalism and
anthropomorphism in comparative psychology. His principle stated that,
"In no case may we interpret an action as the outcome of the exercise of
a higher psychical faculty, if it can be interpreted as the outcome of
the exercise of one which stands lower in the psychological scale"
(1894, p. 53). Morgan acknowledged that, "we are forced, as men, to
gauge the psychical level of the animal in terms of the only mind of
which we have first-hand knowledge, namely the human mind" (1894, p.
55). However, he also argued that the principles of evolution forced a
recognition that different species would possess different "psychical
faculties" in different degrees. This included the possibility that an
animal species could possess a faculty in a higher degree than does a
human. This "method of variation" as Morgan called it, was "the least
anthropomorphic, and therefore the most difficult" (1894, p. 58) of the
alternatives he considered for understanding animals. Notwithstanding
his desire to constrain anthropomorphism, Morgan remained committed to a mentalistic interpretation of animal behavior. In the Preface to his
book he wrote, "It would be an inestimable boon to comparative
psychology, if all those who venture to discuss the problems with which
this science deals would submit to some preparatory discipline in the
methods and results of introspective observation" (1894, p. xii). Morgan
agreed entirely with Romanes that "the human mind [be used] as a key by
which to read the brute mind." What Morgan sought was not a parsimony
that eschewed mentalism in the study of animal minds, but rather a
parsimonious mentalism for comparative psychology. George Miller (1962)
accurately encapsulated Morgan’s position thus: "all that Morgan hoped
for were a few reasonable rules for playing the anthropomorphic game."
The American, Edward Thorndike, took the next step
towards ridding animal psychology of mentalism and anthropomorphism in
his Animal Intelligence (1911). Thorndike is widely credited with
introducing the experimental method to the study of animal psychology.
He was a scathing critic of the mentalistic anthropomorphic explanations
of animal behavior that had preceded him, but he was not altogether free
of these tendencies himself. When discussing problem-solving in capuchin
monkeys, for example, Thorndike wrote: "Monkeys seem to enjoy strange
places; they revel, if I may be permitted an anthropomorphism, in novel
objects. They like to have feelings as they do to make movements. The
fact of mental life is to them its own reward" (1911, p. 238).
It was John B. Watson who totally rejected
anthropomorphism in his Behaviorism of 1913. Watson considered
the approach of Darwin, Romanes and Morgan, working by analogy from
human consciousness to animal experience, "absurd."
Any other hypothesis than that which admits the
independent value of behavior material, regardless of any bearing
such material may have upon consciousness, will inevitably force us
to the absurd position of attempting to construct the
conscious content of the animal whose behavior we have been
studying. On this view, after having determined our animal’s
…various problems and its various ways of solving them -- we should
still feel that the task is unfinished and that the results are
worthless, until we can interpret them by analogy in the light of
consciousness. …Surely this doctrine which calls for an analogical
interpretation of all behavior data may be shown to be false: the
position that the standing of an observation upon behavior is
determined by its fruitfulness in yielding results which are
interpretable only in the narrow realm of (really human)
consciousness (Watson, 1913, p. 159).
Watson’s prohibition on anthropomorphism echoed the
thirteenth century condemnation of anthropomorphism as a way of
understanding god and the angels. Anthropomorphism had come to stand for
mentalistic, folk-psychological ways of understanding animals, and the
new objective science of behaviorist psychology stood for the removal of
these older ways of thinking.
Ethology
In the 1930s, an alternative school for the objective
study of animal behavior grew up outside psychology departments. The
discipline of ethology defined itself in large part in opposition to the
psychological approach of its day. Ethologists studied (and still prefer
to study) the spontaneous, species-typical behaviors of a range of
animal species in their natural habitats – or close simulacra. This
stands in contrast to psychologists who more typically study behaviors
which are conserved across species in a small set of animals kept in
artificial laboratory environments.
In defining ethology, however, the founders of that
field, Niko Tinbergen and Konrad Lorenz, held on to one tenant of the
behaviorist psychology to which they were in many other ways
ideologically opposed. They wanted theirs to be an objective science of
behavior and rejected mentalism and anthropomorphism outright.
Tinbergen, in the volume that defined the field of ethology, The
Study of Instinct (1951), wrote: "Because subjective phenomena
cannot be observed objectively in animals, it is idle either to claim or
to deny their existence." At a conference in 1959 he expressed himself
even more strongly: according to Richard Burkhardt (2005, p. 434),
"[Tinbergen’s] commitment to the objective study of behavior [w]as ‘a
matter of principle with no compromise possible.’ He commented further:
‘Some may say our view is very narrow. All right, it is narrow; but we
feel we must recognize that science is a limited occupation and is only
one way of meeting nature.’" Lorenz may not have been quite as committed
to keeping mentalism out of ethology but he allowed himself to be swayed
by Tinbergen on this matter. As Gordon Burghardt put it, "Lorenz put it
on the back burner, whereas Tinbergen ordered it out of the kitchen"
(Burghardt, 1985, p. 909).
Therefore, the rise of ethology alone does not seem
to have greatly changed attitudes towards mentalism in psychology, in
general, and comparative psychology, in particular. However, the
addition of the cognitive revolution to ethology seems to have set up
the conditions for this change. George Miller has characterized the rise
of cognitive views as a "counterrevolution:…the cognitive
counter-revolution in psychology brought the mind back into experimental
psychology" (Miller, 2003, p. 141). This revolution in psychology, which
most people date from the 1950s and 1960s, was slow to make its presence
felt on the study of animals. By the mid 1970s, however, students of
animal behavior were taking an interest in cognitive approaches. One
direction this took, especially among psychologists, was a renewed
interest in intervening variables (e.g., Hulse, Fowler, & Honig, 1978).
Such variables are derived from observed behavior and not intrinsically
anthropomorphic. The other direction was laid out by ethologist Donald
Griffin, famous for his discovery of the echo navigation of bats in the
1940s, in his The Question of Animal Awareness, 1976. Though the
origins of Griffin’s ideas are obscure, according to an obituary by one
of his students, Griffin was more influenced by the complexity of animal
behavior combined with discussions with Princeton philosopher Robert
Nagel than by anything coming out of psychology at that time (Gould,
2004). In his "thin but deeply subversive volume" (Gould, 2004, p. 1)
Griffin introduced the term "cognitive ethology." He laid out his
position thus:
Ethologists and comparative psychologists have
discovered increasing complexities in animal behavior during the
past few decades…The flexibility and appropriateness of such
behavior suggest not only that complex processes occur within animal
brains, but that these events may have much in common with our own
mental experiences…this book will examine both the pertinent
evidence and its general significance in the hope of stimulating
renewed interest in, and investigation of, the possibility that
mental experiences occur in animals and have important effects on
behavior (1976, p. 3-4).
Griffin’s form of dualism, where ‘consciousness’ is
an information processing ability in addition to the activity of the
brain, has not found many followers. Allen and Bekoff, (1997, p. 153)
refer to, "…Griffin’s puzzling view that consciousness might help
organisms such as honeybees by compensating for the limited processing
power afforded by their relatively small nervous systems." But Griffin’s
general push for more tolerance for mentalistic anthropomorphism has
found much support from researchers under the rubric of "cognitive
ethology" and to some degree in the new field of "animal cognition."
Modern Anthropomorphism
Several authors have attempted to meld the discipline
of the objective schools of animal behavior such as behaviorism and
classical ethology with the freedom to consider mental processes put
forward by Griffin. In doing so, they have proposed modified forms of
anthropomorphism. Foremost among those trying to make anthropomorphism
do useful work for comparative psychologists and ethologists is Gordon
Burghardt (1985; 1991; 2004; Rivas & Burghardt, 2002). Rivas and
Burghardt suggest that, "Like the poor, anthropomorphism will always be
with us" (2002, p. 9) but they argue that not all anthropomorphism is
bad. The kind of anthropomorphism that must be avoided by serious
students of animal behavior is unwitting "naïve anthropomorphism." This
is when someone allows their natural tendency to see living things as
having a human-like mentality to operate in an "unacknowledged,
unrecognized [form], or used as the basis for accepting conclusions by
circumventing the need to actually test them" (2002, p. 10).
This relates to the concept of "anthropomorphism by
omission." Rivas and Burghardt (2002) define this as the error of
"omitting to put oneself in the animal’s shoes" (p. 11). Burghardt
(1985) gives as an example the study of vervet monkey vocalizations.
Prior to the work of Cheney and Seyfarth (1982) it was believed that
these monkeys’ social grunts lacked semantic content because they all
sounded similar to the human ear. On closer study, however, it
transpired that other monkeys recognized four different signals in these
grunts which had all sounded similar to humans. In this sense, according
to Burghardt, science progresses better when scientists think themselves
into the position of the animal under study.
Burghardt argues for a form of anthropomorphism,
which he calls "critical anthropomorphism" (1991, p. 86) that is not a
logical error. He defines critical anthropomorphism as a way of using
the assumption that animals have private experiences, "to formulate
research agendas that result in publicly verifiable data that move our
understanding of behavior forward" (1991, p. 86). This view is similar
to that espoused by Edward Tolman (1938) who stated:
...there seems to me every advantage in
beginning by conceiving the situation loosely and
anthropomorphically.... in my future work [I] intend to go ahead
imagining how, if I were a rat, I would behave as a result of
such and such a demand combined with such and such an appetite and
such and such a degree of differentiation; and so on. And then, on
the basis of such imaginings, I shall try to figure out some sort of
... rules or equations (p. 24; emphasis in original).
Burghardt and Rivas’ concept of "anthropomorphism by
omission" is similar to what Frans de Waal calls "anthropodenial... a
blindness to the humanlike characteristics of other animals, or the
animal-like characteristics of ourselves" (de Waal, 1997, p. 51; 2002).
De Waal advocates "animal-centered anthropomorphism." Like Burghardt and
Tolman, de Waal argues for "a tolerant attitude toward the borrowing of
human concepts to explain animal behavior." He argues that
"anthropomorphism ought to be a nonissue in the case of anthropoid apes.
But even in the case of more distant species, anthropomorphic
explanations deserve serious attention." Nonetheless he adds, "We should
never accept explanations without critical reflection, but there is
nothing wrong with widening the workspace of permissible hypotheses
while retaining high standards of replicability and scientific scrutiny"
(1999, p. 274).
Another recent reviver of anthropomorphism, Mark
Bekoff, argues that "anthropomorphism allows other animals’ behavior and
emotions to be accessible to us" (2000, p. 867). Acknowledging that
unthinking anthropomorphism is not scientific, Bekoff (2000) argues for
"biocentric anthropomorphism," which is compatible with "rigorous
science" (p. 867). Particularly in the realm of emotions, Bekoff
suggests that using anthropomorphism - applying human labels to animal
behaviors - causes little harm, whereas, "...closing the door on the
possibility that many animals have rich emotional lives, ...will lose
great opportunities to learn about the lives of animals..." (p. 869).
A related but distinct concept is that of
"Theromorphism" (Timberlake, 1999, p. 256). Timberlake argues for
animal-centered rather than anthropomorphic observation. Animal-centered
observation implies putting oneself into the position of the animal
under study but not in an anthropomorphic way. Rather, Timberlake argues
for a complete objective understanding of the animal’s position. He
contrasts this with anthropomorphic television programs that show us
wild animals with a voice-over talking of the animals entirely as one
would a human being in the same circumstances. Timberlake (1999) uses
hunting lions as an example:
[we]...are asked to imagine skulking through the
tall dry grass of the veldt--feeling the brush of the stalks, the
looming heat of the sun... we exchange significant looks with our
sisters and so coordinate a successful ambush to procure a fresh
meal from a nearby heard of zebras (p. 255).
(Timberlake notes that we are not invited to
"...imagine how it feels to break the back of the zebra, eat its
entrails while it lives...".) Such imaginings, Timberlake notes, can be
of no use to a scientific approach. What Timberlake argues for with his
animal-centered theromorphism is to take the point of view of the
lioness, "but as a lioness, not a human" (p. 256). Thus, we must ask
about the sensory, perceptual and responsive worlds of the lion qua
lion. The theomorphic approach differs from the anthropomorphic because
it "is based on convergent information from behavior, physiology, and
the results of experimental manipulations" (p. 256).
I mention Timberlake’s theromorphism only for the
sake of completeness and as an example of a viable way forward. It does
not, in my opinion, suffer the drawbacks of the "true" anthropomorphisms
because it eschews mentalism. What the true anthropomorphisms share is a
belief that the imaginative projection of one’s mentalistic self into
the life of a member of another species can lead to the production of
hypotheses which may prompt the production of useful objective data.
The Emperor’s New Anthropomorphism
What could be wrong with the new anthropomorphisms? I
accept that critical, animal-centered, biocentric anthropomorphism may
be close to what Darwin had in mind when he wrote about animal
psychology. They are explicitly evolutionary attempts to understand
animal minds by exploiting the analogies that must exist between human
and nonhuman psychology. However, I believe there are two things wrong
with anthropomorphism from which the more recent reformulations by
Bekoff, Burghardt, and de Waal still cannot free us.
The first concerns the names for things and might for
that reason be dismissed as relatively unimportant. However, the names
we give to ideas do influence how we think about them, so I think this
point is worth raising. Since Bishop Tempier’s Condemnations in the
thirteenth century, "anthropomorphism" has stood for a flawed way of
thinking. According to Chambers’ Cyclopædia; or, an Universal
Dictionary of Arts and Sciences—Supplement (1753),
"anthropomorphism" is described as, "…the error of those who ascribe a
human figure to the deity" (as cited in the Oxford English Dictionary
online, 2006). Thus I think it a mistake to try and take this word and
make it stand for a positive way of considering the relationship between
human and animal psychology.
More importantly, these new forms of anthropomorphism
still represent a mentalistic approach to animal psychology. Mentalism
is a form of folk psychology – a set of pre-scientific beliefs about how
people function (Nichols, 2002; Ravenscroft, 2004). It is not a
component of modern objective psychology. It is not only behaviorism
that dismissed mentalism, but ethology too. Contemporary human cognitive
psychology, though it has resurrected several mentalistic concepts, is
nonetheless an objective materialistic science seeking insights through
experiment (see Neisser, 1967). Though introspection is sometimes used
by cognitive psychologists as a source of hypotheses, these hypotheses
have to be experimentally tested before they are considered scientific
theories. In addition, while there are grounds for criticising
mentalistic introspection as a tool even in human psychology, the issues
are not as extreme as when this method is applied across species.
Darwin’s mentalistic focus in seeking analogies
between human and animal psychology is readily understood given the
period in history when he was writing. At Darwin’s death in 1882, the
empirical and objective science of psychology was still in its infancy
(Wundt, 1874/1904, is probably the first textbook of an empirical
psychology and the only one published in Darwin’s lifetime), and an
empirical science of animal psychology had yet to be born (Thorndike,
1898, is arguably the earliest experimental study of animal psychology).
Consequently, that Darwin, in arguing for commonalities in the
psychology of humans and animals, used mentalistic folk-psychological
terms is completely comprehensible within the framework available to him
then.
A century and a half later, scientists interested in
animal psychology do not have to appeal to mentalistic,
folk-psychological explanations of behavior to make sense of the
commonalities between humans and animals which evolution tells us to
expect. Mentalism fails to qualify as a scientific explanation for (at
least) two reasons. First, it uses ultimately non-material causes to
attempt to explain behavior. It goes outside the physical world in its
search for explanations. Second, mentalistic concepts are intrinsically
private and thus by definition subjective, not objective. Today we not
only have objective concepts from behaviorist psychology, but also from
ethology, behavioral ecology and cognitive psychology, which, because of
their more objective basis, form a much better platform for explaining
animal behavior.
A Shaggy Dog Story
Consider the behavior of a domestic dog when its
owner returns home to find something broken in the house. Most dog
owners, confronted with these circumstances, have seen the
characteristic submissive posture in dogs which Darwin described thus:
"dogs not only lower their bodies and crouch a little as they approach
their masters, but sometimes throw themselves on the ground with their
bellies upwards. This is a movement as completely opposite as is
possible to any show of resistance" (Darwin, 1872, p. 120). The fact
that dogs will show this posture if they have broken something while the
owner was out of the house might be viewed as supporting Darwin’s belief
that "dogs possess something very like a conscience" (Darwin, 1871, p.
103).
From the anthropomorphic perspective this might be
considered an adequate explanation. If a person behaves submissively
("regretfully") when they have broken something that belongs to somebody
else, we might, in everyday language, ascribe to them "remorse" and
consider our explanation closed. Thus, if we are thinking
anthropomorphically – even with critical or animal-centered
anthropomorphism – we put ourselves imaginatively into the paws of the
dog and hypothesize that the dog too experiences remorse.
The problem with an anthropomorphic explanation of
this form is that nothing has been explained. There is no science of
"remorse" to which we have appealed. Even as an explanation of human
behavior, "remorse" is vacuous; it lacks any power to predict or control
future behavior. We have committed the nominalist fallacy – the belief
that to give something a name is to explain it (Blumberg & Wasserman,
1995). Far better putative hypotheses to explain a dog’s behavior under
these circumstances can be drawn from objective sciences of animal
behavior such as behaviorist or cognitive psychology and ethology.
I have noticed that young puppies do not show any
submissive behavior in the presence of a damaged object until they have
been chastised at least once upon the discovery of damage. Furthermore,
a sensitive dog may show submissive behavior when its master returns
home to something broken, even in cases where the owner knows that the
dog is not responsible for the breakages. These two observations suggest
an alternative hypothesis. Perhaps the dog is subject to Pavlovian
conditioning. Perhaps the broken object is a conditioned stimulus. It is
initially neutral, but when paired with chastisement (the unconditioned
stimulus) it comes to evoke a response of its own. That response being
the conditioned response – in the dog’s case a submissive posture. The
fact that a dog, under these circumstances, adopts a particular posture
as the conditioned response would appeal to knowledge about animal
behavior drawn from ethology. That the dog does not produce this
conditioned response unless and until the master returns home suggests
that higher-order processes sometimes labeled "cognitive," perhaps
occasion-setting (Holland, 1992), may be at work.
An explanation like this, that weds Pavlovian
conditioning with ethological knowledge and contributions from animal
cognition, leads directly to testable predictions. If the process
involved really is Pavlovian conditioning, then other Pavlovian
phenomena, like blocking and overshadowing (Pearce, 1997) should be
uncoverable under the right conditions. The fact that a species-typical
submissive posture is involved implies that other species should show
different characteristic behaviors under similar circumstances. Of
course tests for Pavlovian phenomena and tests derived from ethological
concepts could prove my armchair hypothesizing wrong. This, however,
only shows the strength of the approach, not its weakness. It could well
be the submissive behavior of a dog under these circumstances is in fact
an instance of operant conditioning, or better understood solely in
terms of species typical reactions to dominant individuals without any
appeal to learning processes. Whatever the case might turn out to be,
this empirical approach, without appeal to mentalistic,
folk-psychological notions, is the one that will lead to testable
hypotheses and an objective understanding of animal behavior.
This style of explanation is no less Darwinian in the
broader sense than an explanation in terms of "remorse." Humans too show
Pavlovian conditioning, higher-level cognitive processes, and species
typical behaviors. This explanatory sketch will function just as well as
an attempt to explain remorse in human beings as in dogs. I am inclined
to think that it is more likely to be a successful account of dog
behavior than of human behavior, but an advantage of this approach is
that it could well lead to a more nuanced understanding of how what we
casually call "remorse" in humans shares qualities with, and also
differs from, what some might call "remorse" in dogs.
It is my impression that human children more readily
discriminate cases where they are responsible for damage from cases
where the breakages are not their responsibility, but this is an
empirical question. They also, as any parent knows, develop verbal
behaviors in an effort to deflect their chastisement onto other
individuals. These verbal abilities also enable humans to connect one
experience of "remorse" to many others, not only of their own but also
those of other people, including people they may never meet. This
enriches the concept very greatly.
|
Figure 8. Sybille (1993 – 2004). The
author’s cat. After some years, Sybille indicated she was tired
of having her thoughts interpreted anthropomorphically and
expressed a desire to be considered a Cartesian automaton. |
The account I am putting forward may take a moment
longer to explain than just saying "remorse" but it is nonetheless more
parsimonious because it does not require the postulation of any new
principles – it relies on principles well established from other
studies. In addition, it is a scientific explanation that leads to
predictions and may be proven wrong. Maybe this is operant conditioning,
not classical. Maybe it does not have anything to do with the species
typical cowering posture to a dominant animal. All these are testable
empirical hypotheses. "Remorse" is not. There is no science of remorse.
I am not concerned that this explanation in terms of
conditioning and species-typical reactions is not the one that Darwin
would have proposed. Darwin’s writings on animal psychology are now well
over one hundred years old. No geneticist today appeals to Darwin’s
notions of inheritance. Similarly, the terms in which Darwin discussed
psychology are now seriously outdated. That does not make his central
insights any less valid. Geneticists evince no embarrassment in talking
about modern, empirically derived concepts of inheritance within a
Darwinian framework, and comparative psychologists should feel no
different in using modern, objective concepts of animal behavior within
that same framework.
Concluding Thoughts
Anthropomorphism comes very naturally to human
beings. We must be continuously on our guard against it. Small children
will label any self-propelled or animal-shaped object with human agency
(Serpell, 2003). The combination of both qualities creates objects that
even adults have difficulty not interpreting in human terms. However,
anthropomorphism must be resisted. Its drawbacks remain the same as they
have always been: mentalistic folk-psychological accounts of animal
psychology have no useful role to play in a modern objective science.
They are non-material explanations which are the products of folk
psychology and as such are not amenable to objective study. As I put it
once before, "the reintroduction of anthropomorphism risks bringing back
the dirty bathwater as we rescue the baby" (Wynne, 2004). The study of
animal cognition will only proceed effectively once it rids itself of
pre-scientific notions like anthropomorphism.
Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (1997). Species of
mind: The philosophy and biology of cognitive ethology.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Bekoff, M. (2000). Animal emotions: Exploring
passionate natures. BioScience, 50, 861-870.
Blumberg, M. S., & Wasserman, E. A. (1995).
Animal mind and the argument from design. American Psychologist,
50, 133-144.
Boakes, R. (1984). From Darwin to
behaviourism: Psychology and the minds of animals. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Browne, J. (2003). Charles Darwin: The power
of place. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Burghardt, G. M. (1985). Animal awareness:
Current perceptions and historical perspective. American
Psychologist, 40, 905-919.
Burghardt, G. M. (1991). Cognitive ethology and
critical anthropomorphism: A snake with two heads and hognose snakes
that play dead. In C. A. Ristau (Ed.), Cognitive ethology: The
minds of other animals: Essays in honor of Donald R. Griffin
(pp. 53-90). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Burghardt, G. M. (2004). Ground rules for dealing
with anthropomorphism. Nature, 430, 15.
Burkhardt, R. (2005). Patterns of behavior:
Konrad Lorenz, Niko Tinbergen, and the founding of ethology.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Cheney, D. M., & Seyfarth, R. M. (1982).
Recognition of individuals within and between groups of freeranging
vervet monkeys. American Zoologist, 22, 519-530.
Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by
means of natural selection or the preservation of favored races in
the struggle for life. London: John Murray.
Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man, and
selection in relation to sex. London: John Murray.
Darwin, C. (1872). The expression of emotions
in man and animals. London: John Murray.
Daston, L. (2005). Intelligences: Angelic,
animal, human. In L. Daston & G. Mitman (Eds.), Thinking with
animals: New perspectives on anthropomorphism. New York, NY:
Columbia University Press.
de Waal, F. (1997). Are we in anthropodenial?
Discover, 18, 50-53.
de Waal, F. (1999). Anthropomorphism and
anthropodenial: Consistency in our thinking about humans and other
animals. Philosophical Topics, 27, 255-280.
de Waal, F. (2001). The ape and the sushi
master: Cultural reflections of a primatologist. New York, NY:
Basic Books.
Gould, J. L. (2004). Thinking about thinking: How
Donald R. Griffin (1915–2003) remade animal behavior. Animal
Cognition, 7, 1-4.
Griffin, D. R. (1976). The question of animal
awareness: Evolutionary continuity of mental experience. New
York: Rockefeller University Press.
Holland, P. (1992). Occasion setting in Pavlovian
conditioning. In D. L. Medin (Ed.), The psychology of learning
and motivation. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Hulse, S., Fowler, H., & Honig, W. (Eds.).
(1978). Cognitive processes in animal behavior. Mahweh, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Lewes, G. H. (1860). Seaside studies at
Ilfracombe, Tenby, the Scilly Isles, and Jersey (2nd ed.).
Edinburgh: William Blackwood & Sons.
Miller, G. A. (1962). Psychology, the science
of mental life. New York: Harper & Row.
Miller, G.A. (2003). The cognitive revolution: A
historical perspective. Trends In Cognitive Sciences, 7,
141-144.
Morgan, C. L. (1894). Introduction to
comparative psychology. London, UK: Walter Scott Ltd.
Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology.
New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Nichols, S. (2002). Folk psychology. In
Encyclopedia of cognitive science. London: Nature Publishing
Group.
Pearce, J. (1997). Animal learning and
cognition: An introduction (2nd ed.). Hove, UK: Psychology
Press.
Ravenscroft, I. (2004). Folk psychology as a
theory. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Retrieved from
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2004/entries/folkpsych-theory/.
Rivas, J., & Burghardt, G. M. (2002).
Crotalomorphism: A metaphor for understanding anthropomorphism by
omission. In M. Bekoff, C. Allen, & G. M. Burkhardt (Eds.), The
cognitive animal: Experimental and theoretical perspectives on
animal cognition (pp. 9-17). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Romanes, G. (1883). Animal intelligence.
New York: D. Appleton & Co.
Serpell, J.A. (2003). Anthropomorphism and
anthropomorphic selection - beyond the "cute response." Society &
Animals, 11(1), 83-100.
Skinner, B. F. (1938). The behavior of
organisms. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
The Oxford English dictionary (2nd ed.).
(1989). Oxford University Press. Retrieved September 26, 2006 from
http://www.oed.com/.
Thorndike, E. L. (1898). Animal intelligence: An
experimental study of the association processes in animals.
Psychological Review Monograph, 2 (Whole No. 8).
Thorndike, E. L. (1911). Animal intelligence:
Experimental studies. New York, NY: Macmillan.
Timberlake, W. (1999). Biological behaviorism. In
W. O’Donohue & R. Kitchener (Eds.), Handbook of behaviorism
(pp. 243-284). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Tinbergen, N. (1951). The study of instinct.
Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Tolman, E. (1938). The determiners of behavior at
a choice point. Psychological Review, 45, 1-41.
Wallace, A. R. (1869). Geological climates and
the origin of species. Quarterly Review, 126, 359-394.
Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the
behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20, 158-177.
Wundt, W. (1904). Principles of physiological
psychology. (E. B. Titchener, Trans.). London: Swan Sonnenschein.
(Original work published in 1874).
Wynne, C. D. L. (2004). The perils of
anthropomorphism. Nature, 428, 606.