The MIT scientist Donald Griffin, widely-recognized
for his experimental confirmation that bats use echo location in
tracking insects and avoiding obstacles in the dark (Griffin,
1958/1974), later wrote widely defending the view that other animals are
consciously aware and intelligent, like humans (Griffin, 1976, 2001).
Based on the assumption that an example of possible human-like
cleverness in another animal species establishes the presence of both
consciousness and intelligence, Griffin extended the continuum of
human-like consciousness to many other species. For example, Griffin
believed the assassin bug was conscious and intelligent because it could
be viewed as disguising itself (by sticking the drained bodies of prey
on its exoskeleton) before lying in wait for new victims. Griffin’s
focus on the anthropomorphic inference of presumed intentional
cleverness in other animals provided an important impetus for similar
inference of human-like animal consciousness in areas ranging from
cognitive ethology to animal personality.
Given the extreme diversity of opinion in this area
of thinking and research, it is not surprising that Griffin’s (1976,
2001) view has not been universally accepted. In a recent Nature
note titled, "The Perils of Anthropomorphism," Clive Wynne (2004)
strongly objected to Griffin’s approach, warning that "…the
reintroduction of anthropomorphism risks bringing back the dirty
bathwater as we rescue the baby." In the present follow up article
("What are animals? Why anthropomorphism is still not a scientific
approach to behavior"), Wynne supports his argument further with
historical details about the concept of anthropomorphism, and critical
attention to the views of scientists who have offered modified versions
of anthropomorphism, including Gordon Burghardt’s (1991) concept of
critical anthropomorphism, Franz de Waal’s (1997, 2001) animal-centered
anthropomorphism, and Marc Bekoff’s (2000) biocentric anthropomorphism.
In this commentary I focus on the question of whether
the scientific community should completely reject the concept and
practice of anthropomorphism as subjective story-telling, or if there
may be aspects of anthropomorphism worth integrating with current
scientific approaches. For example, Burghardt, de Waal, and Bekoff
support components of seeming anthropomorphic-like inferences, so it
appears they think there is something worth saving about attempts to
enter an animal’s world. Further, as several authors have noted, the
British naturalist Lloyd-Morgan, long credited with an Occam’s razor
view of consciousness, clearly felt anthropomorphism was suitable in
some cases. Even Wynne’s (2004) concern (in the quote above) with
rescuing the baby from the bathwater suggests the possibility that he
also finds something potentially worthwhile in this area. Finally, based
on the history of ideas, it seems clear that calls to abandon completely
a concept with a long history of use, like anthropomorphism, may profit
from a more careful analysis of its contributions.
Anthropomorphism and Social Tool Kits
Webster’s (1975) defines anthropomorphism as "an
interpretation of what is not human or personal in terms of human or
personal characteristics." This is usually understood to mean the
assignment of human emotions, cognitions, intentions, and planning to
whatever species we are observing. Perhaps the most interesting question
about anthropomorphism is why it remains so frequent and widespread? The
simplest answer appears to be Colin Beer’s (1980) argument that during
the evolution of our species, our gene pool has given rise to a social
tool kit consisting of tendencies to attribute beliefs, perceptions,
emotions, and intentions to other human and nonhuman animals, presumably
allowing us to predict as well as manipulate their behavior.
To my eye, the observational and experimental
literatures suggest that many social vertebrates share elements of a
mental attribution tool kit, but that social primates, particularly
baboons and the great apes, show greater complexity in attributing and
successfully behaving so as to manipulate the intentions, goals, and
beliefs of other species members. These attribution capabilities appear
to have been further enhanced in Homo sapiens, probably because
of selection pressures resulting from our combination of group hunting,
migration, and defense with the emergence of complex vocal communication
and relatively monogamous reproduction. There are questions about the
independence and order of emergence of these capabilities and the extent
of their dependence on cultural beliefs and artifacts, and environmental
resources, but it seems evident that humans extensively attribute to
other animals attention, beliefs, and goals related to resources (e.g.,
food, sex, and shelter) and dangers (e.g., predators, loss of food,
illness, and social aggression). These tendencies toward anthropomorphic
attribution appear to persist despite being of mixed benefit, arguably
facilitating our successful but potentially disastrous rise in numbers,
and enhancing our flexibility in relating to each other by exaggerating,
distorting, or denying current information.
Rapid and broad engagement is a highly salient aspect
of this human social tool kit (Beer, 1980). For example, Michotte (1963)
showed that humans instantaneously and largely unavoidably perceive and
attribute agency (social relations, motivations, and intentions) to
stimuli in their environment, even artificial stimuli such as the
movement of small, colored squares of light on a screen. In a
potentially related phenomenon, humans throughout history have tended to
attribute their success and failures to the influence of powerful
supernatural beings whose wishes and allegiances are inferred from
environmental events and ambiguous signs. In the present era, many young
males (and some females) invest small pixilated smudges on video game
screens with a full suite of human beliefs, motivations, and goals.
It seems apparent that humans can be characterized as
the species most trigger-happy in attributing mental states to objects,
living entities, and display pixels that move, the species most likely
to view significant environmental and social events as caused by the
intentions and beliefs of another mind, and the species most likely to
blame or credit our own or others’ minds for things that are arguably
outside our control. As if these biases were not enough, we not only use
anthropomorphic labels to explain our own behavior, but we use
anthropomorphic labels for inferred mental events to explain the
behavior of other species. Because most species seem much less likely to
have identifiable beliefs and goals in the same sense that we do, it
seems almost like a conflict of interest (from the point of view of
being unbiased) that we should insist on analyzing their behavior using
our interpretive anthropomorphic framework.
It is as though naked mole rats decided among
themselves that the critical means for interpreting events in other
organisms and themselves was the correct labeling of odors. Suppose
whenever a mole rat scientist established a correlation between a
labeled odor and a behavior (or an odor and a reliable brain activity),
the existence of that behavior (or activity) was taken as evidence for
the causal power of the label that we gave it. It seems important to
show caution in using species-ready perception kits and causal labels to
explain the causation of behavior, perhaps recalling the still useful
adage, "If you have a hammer, everything looks like a nail."
In short, I believe the appropriate conclusion is
that primary dependence on unshackled anthropomorphism for our knowledge
about other species is not a promising direction for science to go. It
may look attractive to some when placed alongside a caricature of the
century-old behaviorist-experimentalist approach. However, when compared
to more recent work in learning, cognition, and neurophysiology, a
primary dependence on anthropomorphic attribution appears to lead toward
automatically adjusting and confirming just-so stories. At the least,
observers using unconstrained anthropomorphism should develop and apply
a form of signal detection analysis to their attribution of intentions,
emotions, goals, and beliefs. Such an analysis should consider rates of
false alarms and misses, as well as apparent hits. However, it seems to
me more appropriate to continue to work on clarifying a more empirical
grounding for understanding the world and predicting the behavior of
other animals.
Empirically-Grounded Approaches to the World and
Behavior of other Animals
Burghardt, de Waal, and, to an extent, Bekoff have
argued for a more empirically grounded approach to anthropomorphism,
where the grounding is informed by specific knowledge we have acquired
about the behavior, ecology, evolution, development, genetics, and
neurophysiology of particular species. The acquiring of knowledge is
scarcely a novel idea, the question is the form in which it arrives, and
how such knowledge can be integrated in a way that predicts behavior.
Laboratory approaches focus on operational definitions, precise
procedures, common apparatus, and quantitative data. Part of what is
missing is a commitment to understanding the animal in its world, its
ecological (evolutionary) niche. As Burghardt (1991) noted, if
scientists are going to work with snakes, they ought to try to "…walk in
the shoes of the snake." This admonition simultaneously highlights the
difficulties and importance of dealing with the world from the point of
view of other animals. Snakes neither walk nor wear shoes, yet we must
provide a framework in which we can do the equivalent of walking in the
snake’s shoes in order to appreciate and predict its behavior. In this
section I will briefly examine several contexts in which humans have
acquired and used knowledge about other species (and in which other
species have simultaneously learned about us), and suggest an analytic
framework that tries to combine successful elements of these approaches.
Farmers, hunters, naturalists, and trainers
This disparate group typically develops their
knowledge of other species by interacting with particular animals over
and over again in circumstances where it is important to predict the
behavior of both species and individuals. The economic livelihood,
personal safety, and effectiveness of these humans depend on developing
and using an accurate model of the likely behavior and motivation of
animals they deal with. It is interesting that many small farmers
frequently classify (and even name) cows on the basis of human-like
characteristics that correlate with their behaviors: for example,
bossiness, meanness, cleverness, wariness, hysteria, stubbornness, and
placidity. But these human-like characteristics are usually limited to
the farmer’s observations of the cows’ reactions to the imposed
environment, rather than an appreciation of the cows’ behavior as
cattle. The result tends toward a meliorated anthropomorphism. Not
unexpectedly, the cows appear much less inclined to interpret the
farmer’s behavior, and that of his canine assistant, as though they were
other cows (bovinomorphism--the attributing of cow goals,
intentions, beliefs, and emotions, to other animals). Instead the cows
appear to adjust to the contingencies and environmental support provided
by the farmer within their world as cows.
Wild animals reliably show similar pragmatism within
their own characteristic worlds in their interactions with other
species. They quickly learn to respond to predictive environmental and
behavioral cues that signal the availability of food, or the likelihood
of unwelcome attention, danger, or constraint. In some cases, a form of
mutualism approaching parasitism can arise between species, seemingly
without relation to anthropomorphism. For example, rove beetles may
over-winter in the nests of particular ant species. The beetles beg for
regurgitated food from the ants by using their front legs and antennae
to produce a copy of the tactile begging patterns of young ants, but
with little indication that the beetles attribute goals, intentions, or
motivations to the ants or to other rove beetles. Each species seems to
have a simple but sufficient predictive model of how the behavior of the
other species interacts with their own.
Ethologists and motivational systems
Ethologists, in many respects, were experimental
naturalists who attempted to account for the observed behavior of
domestic and wild animals by developing a general framework (comprised
of perceptual-motor units and regulatory systems) to typify the sensory
world and behavior of each species appropriate to particular
motivational systems (Tinbergen, 1951). Three factors set ethologists
apart from naturalists: their explicit interest in evolution, their use
of systematic experimental manipulations to analyze the stimuli
controlling particular behaviors, and their organization of these
perceptual-motor structures within the context of motivational
(behavior) systems that helped regulate behavior and the internal
environment.
In a classic analysis, ethologists determined the key
stimulus characteristics that triggered and controlled food begging by
gull chicks expressed as pecking directed at a contrasting spot on a
parent’s lower mandible. Ethologists showed this pecking behavior was
initially so strongly controlled by this stimulus that a young chick
would repeatedly beg from a knitting needle striped with three bands
near the tip and held vertically by the experimenter while moving it
back and forth (Tinbergen, 1951). In such analyses, ethologists often
demonstrated how development, learning, and instinctive aspects of
behavior fit together within motivational systems to produce complex
stimulus sensitivities and strings of search behavior. Thus, any
attribution of goals, beliefs, and intentions occurred within the
context of a motivational system and involved experimental analysis
based on stimulus models developed from previous observations and
experiments.
Experimental psychology and neurophysiology
Early experimental psychologists working with animals
overtly rejected anthropomorphism to emulate physics and physiology by
developing reliable apparatus and procedures that provided general tests
of motivation and learning problems suitable for testing the
psychophysics of sensory reception and the effect of reinforcement
variables on behavior within and between species (e.g., Warden, Jenkins,
& Warner, 1935). These experimenters developed models capable of
producing behavior from combinations of reflexes, motivation, and basic
associative laws. The result was information about thresholds and
discrimination capacities along dimensions ranging from color hue to
numerosity, and measurements of the apparent response-strengthening
effects of deprivation, and reward amount, delay and intermittency.
A shortcoming of this approach, in producing
information that could be used to construct a functional model of the
animal, is that the sensory, motor, and motivational information
produced for each species was embedded in the design of procedures and
apparatus rather than integrated within a model of the functional world
of each species (e.g., Timberlake, 2002). In a sense, the data were
interpreted as though each species represented a different falling body
encountering the same general gravitational field in a vacuum, instead
of a living organism with markedly different surface-to-weight ratios
related to flying, gliding, swimming, and drifting capabilities, each
suited to different wind and surface conditions and motivational
functions.
Experimenters interested in neuroscience also focused
initially on abstract causal concepts like motivation, reinforcement,
intelligence, control centers in the hypothalamus, cortical
organization, and critical neuronal transmitters. More recently,
neurophysiologists have begun to approach the brain more functionally by
studying specific survival problems, like how targeting of sounds occurs
in barn owls (e.g., Carew, 2000), and the integration of information
streams in the brain involving sensory input, memory, and interoceptive
information (e.g., Singer, 1998). The extent of integration of this
information in different species, orders, and phyla may eventually
provide a basis for judging the coherence of motivational systems and
their integration with activities such as planning and awareness.
Theromorphism and Behavior Systems
All these approaches have provided us with knowledge
about the sensory, motor, and motivational worlds of animal species,
knowledge that is relevant to grounding our inferences about the
causality of behavior in other species. The difficulty is that the data
are not well integrated even within a particular level of analysis, much
less across several such levels. In an effort to facilitate the
combination of expert knowledge from practitioners, the evolution-based
functional sensory-behavior models from ethology, the paradigms and
results of experimentalists, and the reductionist accounts of
neuroscientists, I previously introduced the concept of theromorphism
(literally animal-centered knowledge--Timberlake, 1994, 1997, 1999;
Timberlake & Lucas, 1989). The root thero- comes from the Greek
word for animal (therio), which I modified in an attempt to
signal that the approach applies to human as well as nonhuman animals
(for historical reasons the Greek word applies only to nonhuman
animals).
A theromorphic approach attempts to discover and
represent important aspects of an animal’s sensory and motivational
worlds, thus allowing a human experimenter/observer to enter the
animal’s world and predict, using descriptive, deductive, and
inferential abilities, the effects of a given set of environmental
conditions on short and long-term behavior of a particular individual
and species. In this way, inferences and attributions of motivation and
function, intentions, and predictions of behavior are grounded in the
knowledge embodied in a behavior system model. This approach relates to
those of Burghardt and de Waal in being animal-centered, but it attempts
to specify a general framework to guide acquiring, storing, and testing
knowledge of an animal’s world. This approach by no means answers all
problems in accounting for behavior, but I believe it is useful in
structuring our knowledge.
A major potential advantage of theromorphism is that
any attribution of mental state and prediction of behavior must be
specifically constrained by what is currently known about the
sensory-motor and motivational systems of the species and animal
involved. This is intended to help the observer limit the use of
inference and prediction capabilities to circumstances in which
something of the perceptual-motor and motivational components and
mechanisms are known and specifically considered. For example, in many
experimental paradigms, a behavior systems model clarifies why specific
combinations of stimuli and responses produce results and others do not,
and how motivational state may change over time or distance from the
goal. This approach allows immediate integration of the results of
current experiments into a functional framework that relates to other
experimental data by providing a common framework for predictions and
attributions of similarities and differences among individuals and
species.
An obvious obstacle to the use of a theromorphic
framework is the time needed to establish it. Naturalists often prefer
more anthropomorphic frameworks, while experimentalists prefer
procedural frameworks relating abstract concepts of stimuli, responses,
and reinforcers. Developing a behavior system seems like a great deal of
unnecessary bother compared to intuiting the intentions and beliefs of
an animal, or manipulating associative variables that control learning
in a well-known apparatus. However, anyone who has worked with an animal
in an applied setting constructs at least a rudimentary version of an
applicable behavior system, consisting of motivational, perceptual, and
motor information, along with some notion of what behavior switching
take place. Similarly, experimentalists who develop and alter laboratory
apparatus and procedures rapidly become aware that a great deal of
knowledge about the functioning of a species has been built into the
apparatus and procedures used with them. Speaking from my experience,
scientists who modify common apparatus and procedures often become
painfully impressed with the species-specific knowledge of the people
who originally fabricated the apparatus and designed the procedures.
In a brief review of the relation of maze paradigms
and procedures to behavior in the rat, Timberlake (2002) examined
important species knowledge built into common maze apparatus and
procedures by using a procedure similar to reverse engineering in the
physical sciences. Based on the assumption that experimenter tuning of
apparatus and procedures has been an important contributor to the
results, it follows that systematically modifying (detuning) the
apparatus and procedures should reveal those aspects of the system that
contributed the most to a particular outcome. For example, in a series
of studies analyzing the mechanisms determining the behavior of rats in
a standard radial arm maze, we showed that the food reward typically
placed at the end of each arm is not a necessary condition for efficient
search of the maze. A more important environmental contributor appears
to be the presence of edges for the arms (that can be contacted by
whiskers), and equal spacing between the arms (see Timberlake, 2002).
Based on these and other manipulations and data, it seems evident that
specific perceptual-motor and regulatory components of species-typical
behavior systems often (if not always) underlie the reliable learned
behavior occurring in common effective laboratory paradigms.
Anthropomorphism Reconsidered
I agree with Burghardt’s (1991) observation that
anthropomorphism will always (automatically) be with us. We are an
unusually social species with complex and changeable alliances and
interactions, and mobile faces that advertently and inadvertently reveal
emotions, beliefs, and likely future actions. These characteristics play
important roles in social status, reproduction, and defense, so humans
are unlikely to quit using them entirely, based either on personal
decision or evolutionary change. However, given the important advantages
of an analytic approach to an animal’s world demonstrated by
naturalists, ethologists, and others, it appears that it might be
profitable to constrain our attributional tendencies within a behavior
systems framework that provides a systematic way to select,
contextualize, and compare our knowledge about particular species, as
well as to efficiently guide knowledge that we subsequently gain.
Such a framework can allow experimenters and
practitioners to model an animal’s world in a way that coordinates its
behavior with apparatus, procedures, function, and evolution. Most
importantly, it should allow us to ground our powerful anthropomorphic
abilities in specific perceptual motor and regulatory mechanisms of
another species so we can take their point of view in interactions with
and within less constrained social and physical environments.
Could a theromorphic approach help us decide on the
consciousness of a species with a world as remote from us as that of an
assassin bug? Based on the comparison of human and assassin bug
neurophysiology, there appears little possibility the assassin bug has
an integrated and flexible state of simultaneous attention to sensory
input, memory, and body state. This suggests our small assassin cannot
be conscious in ways similar to higher vertebrates. However, by
acquiring knowledge of the assassin bug’s neurophysiology,
perceptual-motor modules, search states, and regulatory systems, we
should be able to use our conceptual and anthropomorphic abilities to
enter the world of the assassin bug in a more grounded way. Not based on
attributions of cleverness and planning, or on the assumed presence of
an undefined continuum of consciousness (or, for that matter, based on
associations to the English word, assassin), but through knowledge of an
assassin bug’s sensory-motor and regulatory mechanisms and the support
and contingencies present in the current and evolutionary environment.
As noted above, the apparent drawback of such a
theromorphic approach, with its dependence on behavior systems, is the
considerable work involved in developing the information necessary to
take an animal’s view. Why should we limit ourselves to the development
of a cumbersome conceptual-empirical framework when we can intuit what
is occurring? This question is particularly pertinent when we look at
cases where reflexive anthropomorphism appears both easy and effective,
as in the case of the domestic dog.
Taking a theromorphic view, the intuitive and
instantaneous accuracy we have with respect to judging the attention and
motivation of dogs should be based on similarities in evolved (and
selected) mechanisms of experience, perceptual-motor organization and
motivational systems. Such shared mechanisms should be based in
similarities in vertebrate neurology, mammalian perceptual-motor
organization, and our predatory and social behavior systems. Consider
that the ancestors of both humans and dogs hunted, visually tracked,
chased, and ambushed prey in groups. To a degree, humans and dogs are
both pack animals that live by their wits, hard work, effective social
behavior, and rank. (As an aside, if you are the alleged pack leader of
several dogs, you may wish to discover whether one of them actually
outranks you. According to some trainers, a key sign is whether the dog
places a foot on yours as it sits or stands beside you).
Perhaps most importantly, dogs and humans are well
equipped to share attention based on following the direction of a gaze,
a head turn, or a pointing arm, attending to small gestures and what is
often called body language, and by making loud noises to call attention.
It follows that dogs and humans should find it relatively easy to
interpret and respond to many of each other’s signals and behaviors,
certainly a common observation. Many humans and dogs like to roam around
outside together, go for car rides, chase, play-fight, and watch other
animals. We share with dogs the ability to sing in groups (though dogs
are intentionally slightly off key, humans, at least current humans,
usually try to stay on key).
There are also other differences that make building a
theromorphic model worthwhile. Canids are typically uninterested
in books, photographs, or pixel smudges on display screens, and the
mating system of a stable wild hunting pack typically involves
independent male and female dominance orders and a single breeding pair.
For their part, humans lack a dog’s fascination with squirrels and
desire to roll in excrement and the remains of dead animals. Finally,
most hunting dogs have humans beat when it comes to predicting the path
of prey and reading the postures, weight shifts, and preparatory
movements of other animals. I lived for many years with a female
sight-hound who had studied me carefully, and who knew, before I did,
when I had given in to her unspoken request and was ready to take her
for a "walk." Try as I might, I could not fool her. I think it would be
profitable for science if researchers produced models of the animals
they study as accurate as the model this dog developed of me.
References
Beer, C. G. (1980). Perspectives on animal
behavior comparisons. In M. H. Bornstein (Ed.), Comparative
methods in psychology (pp. 17-64). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Bekoff, M. (2000). Animal emotions: Exploring
passionate natures. Bioscience, 50, 861-870.
Burghardt, G. M. (1991). Ethology and critical anthropomorphism: A
snake with two heads and hognose snakes that play dead. In C. A. Ristau
(Ed.), Cognitive ethology: The minds of other animals: Essays in
honor of Donald R. Griffin (pp. 53-90). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Carew, T. J. (2000). Behavioral neurobiology:
The cellular organization of natural behavior. Sunderland, MA:
Sinauer Associates.
de Waal, F. (1997). Are we in anthropodenial?
Discover, 18, 50-53.
de Waal, F. (2001). The ape and the sushi
master: Cultural reflections of a primatologist. New York, NY:
Basic Books.
Griffin, D. R. (1974). Listening in the dark
(Facsimile Edition). Dover Publications. (Reprinted from Listening
in the dark, 1958, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).
Griffin, D. R. (1976). The question of animal
awareness: Evolutionary continuity of mental experience. New York:
Rockefeller University Press.
Griffin, D. R. (2001). Animal minds: Beyond
cognition to consciousness. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Michotte, A. (1963). The perception of
causality. New York: Basic Books.
Singer, W. (1998). Consciousness and the
structure of neuronal representations. Philosophical Transactions
of the Royal Society of London B., 252, 1829-1840.
Timberlake, W. (1994). Behavior systems,
associationism, and Pavlovian conditioning. Psychonomic Bulletin
& Review, 1, 405-420.
Timberlake, W. (1997). An animal-centered,
causal-system approach to the understanding and control of behavior.
Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 53, 107-129.
Timberlake, W. (1999). Biological behaviorism. In
W. O’Donohue & R. Kitchener (Eds.), Handbook of behaviorism
(pp. 243-284). San Diego: Academic Press.
Timberlake, W. (2002). Niche-related learning in
laboratory paradigms: The case of maze behavior in laboratory rats.
Behavioural Brain Research, 134, 355-374.
Timberlake, W., & Lucas, G. A. (1989). Behavior
systems and learning: From misbehavior to general principles. In S.
B. Klein & R. R. Mowrer (Eds.), Contemporary learning theories:
Instrumental conditioning theory and the impact of biological
constraints on learning (pp. 237-275). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Tinbergen, N. (1951). The study of instinct.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Warden, C. J., Jenkins, T. N., & Warner, L. H.
(1935). Comparative psychology: A comprehensive treatise
(Vol. 1). New York: Ronald Press.
Webster’s New Collegiate Dictionary. (1975).
Springfield, MA: G. & C. Merriam Co.
Wynne, C. D. L. (2004). The perils of anthropomorphism. Nature,
428, 606.
|