|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Concept Learning in Animals |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Thomas R. Zentall University of Kentucky Edward A. Wasserman and Olga F. Lazareva University of Iowa Roger K. R. Thompson Franklin & Marshall College Mary Jo Rattermann University of Indianapolis |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Table 2. Sample Discriminability Design
When a delay is inserted between the sample and comparison stimuli and that delay is varied between trials, one can plot matching accuracy as a function of the duration of the delay. The resulting retention function can provide suggestive evidence for the nature of the underlying representation. For example, following matching-to-sample training with hue samples, the retention functions for pigeons are generally much shallower than they are following line-sample training (Farthing, Wagner, Gilmour, & Waxman, 1977; Urcuioli et al., 1989; Zentall, Urcuioli, Jagielo, & Jackson-Smith, 1989). However, hue and line samples that are associated with the same comparison result in retention functions on line sample trials that are quite similar to those on hue sample trials (see Figure 4; Urcuioli et al., 1989; Zentall et al., 1989), a finding which suggests that the samples have a common representation. 2.3. What is the Nature of the Common Representation? The research on associative classes described to this point provides evidence for the pigeons’ common representation of samples associated with the same comparison. However, identifying the nature of those representations in a nonverbal organism would seem to be a more challenging task than in the case of a verbal human. If two stimuli, A and B, are each associated with a common third stimulus, C, then one possible candidate for the common representation would be a prospective representation of Stimulus C. Thus, seeing either A or B might activate an anticipatory representation of C. But, it is also possible that presentation of one of the samples, say A, activates a representation of the other sample, B, a transformed retrospective representation of the original stimulus. Thus, the common representation may be either a prospective representation of the expected correct comparison stimulus or a retrospective representation of the recently seen sample (Honig & Thompson, 1982). Urcuioli (1996) proposed that a common prospective code in the form of a response intention can account for the transfer of training results reported by Urcuioli et al. (1989) via response mediation (see Table 3). The procedure consisted of two training phases and a testing phase. In Urcuioli’s model, in Phase 1, many-to-one matching training results in, for example, red and vertical-line samples each evoking a representation of the correct comparison stimulus (e.g., circle). Then, during interpolated training in Phase 2, presentation of the red sample continues to evoke a representation of the circle comparison and that representation becomes conditioned to the new correct comparison (e.g., blue). Finally, on test trials, presentation of the vertical-line sample evokes a representation of the correct comparison (circle); but, that representation is now associated with choice of the blue comparison based on interpolated training, so the vertical-sample, blue-comparison association emerges without specific training.
The prospective common-coding hypothesis receives support from the finding that positive transfer has often been found following training with many-to-one matching, but positive transfer typically has not been found following training with one-to-many matching (Urcuioli, 1996). In one-to-many matching, there is one pair of samples and two pairs of comparisons, such that each sample is associated with two comparisons. As can be seen in Table 4, prospective comparison representations cannot mediate the association between the samples that were first experienced during Phase 2 interpolated training and the comparison stimuli that were experienced during Phase 1 training, but not during Phase 2 training. However, there is also growing evidence that, for pigeons, the basis of the representation on a matching trial can be a retrospective representation of one of the samples rather than a prospective representation of one of the comparison stimuli.
Table 3. A mediated generalization account of common coding effects in many-to-one matching
Table 4. The ability of a mediated generalization account of common coding effects to account for the failure to find transfer of training in one-to-many matching.
Perhaps the best evidence for the retrospective coding of samples during many-to-one matching comes from research in which one of the pairs of samples is defined by the presence versus absence of a stimulus (Zentall, Sherburne, & Urcuioli, 1995). Presence versus absence samples can be a hue or a shape versus nothing, or food versus the absence of food. For example, in Zentall et al. (1995), when the sample was food, choice of the vertical-line comparison was correct; but, when the sample was the absence of food (nothing), choice of the horizontal line comparison was correct. On other trials, the samples were red or green and the correct response was to vertical and horizontal lines, respectively. To understand the reasoning behind this experiment requires some background. When samples consist of a pair of stimuli (e.g., red and green), and one introduces a delay between the offset of the sample and the onset of the comparison stimuli, the retention functions for trials involving the two sample types typically appear quite similar to each other and decline gradually to 50% correct choice (e.g., Weaver, Dorrance, & Zentall, 1999). However, when the samples consist of the presence versus the absence of a stimulus, the retention functions for the two samples types typically diverge. Curiously, the retention function on present-sample trials declines rapidly, often to below chance levels of accuracy, whereas the retention function on absent-sample trials typically remains high and flat. This unique pattern of results has been interpreted as evidence that pigeons have developed a single-code/default coding strategy (Colwill, 1984; Grant, 1991; Wilson & Boakes, 1985); that is, on present-sample trials, choice of the comparison associated with the present sample occurs whenever there is a representation of that sample in memory; otherwise, choice of the alternative comparison occurs by default. Thus, on present-sample trials, as the delays increase in duration, memory of the present sample is gradually lost and there is an increasing tendency to respond to the alternative comparison, by default. On absent-sample trials, however, the sample is not encoded; thus, there is no memory loss as the delays increase in duration, and the retention function remains high. Although alternative accounts of this phenomenon have been proposed (see Weaver et al., 1999; Zentall, Kaiser, Clement, Weaver, & Campbell, 2000), for the present purposes, it is not important why those retention functions diverge, only that they do, and that the more typical present-present-sample matching retention functions (e.g., matching-to-sample with red and green samples) do not diverge with increasing delays. We can now examine the rationale for the experiment. Given the differences in retention functions for these two classes of samples, one might be able to identify the nature of the common code by combining present-absent (food/no-food) samples and present-present (red/green) samples in many-to-one matching and by examining the slopes of the resulting retention functions. If pigeons learned to represent the hues as food and its absence, then one would expect both food/no-food retention functions and red/green retention functions to diverge with increasing retention intervals. The retention functions on food-sample trials and on trials involving the hue sample associated with the same comparison as food samples should be steep and the retention functions on no-food-sample trials and on trials involving the hue sample associated with the same comparison as no-food samples should be high and flat. On the other hand, if pigeons represent the food and no-food samples as hues, then one would expect both food/no-food retention functions and red/green retention functions to decline at the same rate and to be superimposed. Zentall et al. (1995) found that the retention functions on food-sample trials were steep and that those on no-food sample trials were flat (i.e., they were divergent as they tend to be when training involves those two samples alone). More important, similar divergent retention functions were found on red and green sample trials (see Figure 5). For the hue sample that was associated with the same comparison as the food sample, the retention function was steep and fell below chance with increasing retention intervals, whereas for the hue sample associated with the same comparison as the no-food sample, the retention function was high and relatively flat. These results suggest that, in the context of many-to-one matching involving food and no-food samples, the remaining red and green samples are coded as retrospective representations of food and its absence. 2.4. Other Procedures for Creating Associative Classes 2.4.1. Common reinforcement history A special case of the common representation of arbitrary stimuli has been reported by Vaughan (1988). In this research, the defining characteristic of each of two stimulus classes (i.e., whether responding to members of one class would be reinforced and whether responding to members of the other class would not) was allowed to vary from session to session of training, such that the value of each class over sessions was the same (members of both classes served equally often as positive, S+, and negative, S-, stimuli). In fact, the only feature that could be used to distinguish between the classes was the reinforcement conditions that were constant within a training session, but that varied between sessions. Vaughan first randomly assigned photographs of trees to two arbitrary sets: A and B. After training pigeons that responses to stimuli in Set A were reinforced and responses to stimuli in Set B were not, the valence associated with each set was reversed, and then reversed again, repeatedly. After a large number of such reversals, Vaughan found that, early in a session (i.e., after a small number of stimuli from each set had been presented), the pigeons would respond appropriately to the remaining members of each set. Thus, these arbitrarily assigned stimuli had become two functional stimulus classes, in spite of the fact that they shared no more in common (in terms of their physical similarity or their overall reinforcement histories) than they did with members of the other class. So, once the current status of each set was determined, the pigeons would respond appropriately to the remaining members. 2.4.2. Symmetry training. An extensive program of research on formal stimulus equivalence began with a now classic experiment by Sidman (1971). Sidman trained a severely retarded child with limited verbal ability to select the appropriate picture of an object when the word for the object was spoken (A-B). The child was also trained to select the written word for an object when the word for the object was spoken (A-C). Sidman found that the child could then select the appropriate picture of an object when presented with the written word for that object (C-B).
In symmetry training, subjects learn that when Stimulus A appears first, it is always followed by Stimulus B and when Stimulus B appears first, it is always followed by Stimulus A. If this procedure effectively establishes the functional equivalence of A and B, then one should be able to train a new association between one of those stimuli (e.g., A) with new Stimulus C and then show that an emergent relation has developed between the remaining stimulus (i.e., B) and new Stimulus C. Zentall et al. (2003) found that such training can in fact result in transfer to a new association when one of those symmetry-trained stimuli is associated with a new stimulus in a matching task and the remaining symmetry-trained stimulus replaces the first (see also, Yamamoto & Asano, 1995). 2.4.3. Formal stimulus equivalence An extensive program of research on formal stimulus equivalence began with a now classic experiment by Sidman (1971). Sidman trained a severely retarded child with limited verbal ability to select the appropriate picture of an object when the word for the object was spoken (A-B). The child was also trained to select the written word for an object when the word for the object was spoken (A-C). Sidman found that the child could then select the appropriate picture of an object when presented with the written word for that object (C-B). Sidman and Tailby (1982) formalized the stimulus equivalence paradigm. They proposed that formal equivalence required that one demonstrate three fundamental stimulus relations. (1) Reflexivity (or generalized identity matching): If trained to select Comparison A after being presented with Sample A, then one would select Comparison B after being presented with Sample B. (2) Symmetry (or bidirectionality): If trained to select Comparison B after being presented with Sample A, then one would select Comparison A after being presented with Sample B. (3) Transitivity (or mediated learning): If trained to select Comparison B after being presented with Sample A and trained to select Comparison C after being presented with Sample B, one would then select Comparison C after being presented with Sample A. Sidman and Tailby (1982) reasoned that if one could show generalized identity matching, then symmetry and transitivity could be demonstrated by training A-B as well as A-C and finding an emergent B-C (or C-B) relation. Later, Sidman (1990) argued that one could show all three properties of formal equivalence by training A-B as well as B-C and demonstrating the emergence of an untrained C-A relation. The reasoning was that an emergent A-C relation would demonstrate transitivity, but an emergent C-A relation would also demonstrate symmetry, and because it implies A-A, reflexivity as well. Such evidence for formal stimulus equivalence has often been found in humans (see Adams, Fields, & Verhave, 1993). It has also been found in California sea lions (Schusterman & Kastak, 1993) and in chimpanzees (Yamamoto & Asano, 1995), but it appears to be difficult to demonstrate in other nonhuman animals such as pigeons. Zentall (1996) proposed that this difficulty is attributable to the directionality imposed by the nature of the conditional discrimination for animals. Specifically, although symmetry training appears to be sufficient to establish functional equivalence, it is difficult to demonstrate an emergent symmetry relation in animals because, in training, the association between sample and correct comparison choice is followed by reinforcement; logically, this is a unidirectional association (but see Frank & Wasserman, 2005). 2.4.4. Learning by exclusion But, it is possible that animals can choose by exclusion yet not learn those specific associations as the result of that experience. Evidence for learning by exclusion requires a more stringent test. Specifically, an animal may choose C3 over C1 when presented with S3 and it may also choose C4 over C2 when presented with S4, but learning by exclusion requires that, when later presented with S3 and a choice between C3 and C4, the animal chooses C3. Kastak and Schusterman have shown just such learning in California sea lions and more recently Kaminski, Call, and Fischer (2004) have found evidence for learning by exclusion in a domestic dog. At least in the simpler situations we are interested in, there are already parallel experiments in the human and animal categorization literatures. However, there are usually multiple procedural differences between experiments on humans and other species, and this makes it hard to interpret any differences in results; in other situations, we have found apparent cross-species differences sometimes dissolve when such procedural differences are removed (Goto, Wills & Lea, 2004). Accordingly, we have embarked on a series of experiments in which we have exposed humans and pigeons to multi-dimensional stimuli in, as far as can reasonably be achieved, identical conditions. Because the animal laboratory is more constraining than human testing, our general strategy has been to develop experimental procedures using pigeons, and then once we have established a robust paradigm, devise the closest human analogue we can. 2.4.5. Functional Classes A functional class is a kind of associative class in which the common association is presumably an acquired function possessed by all of the members of the class (Savage-Rumbaugh, Rumbaugh, Smith, & Lawson, 1980). In the study by Savage-Rumbaugh and her colleagues, chimpanzees were first trained to label a set of objects (bean-cake, orange, and bread) as ‘food’ (edible) and a different set of objects (stick, key, and money) as ‘tools’ (inedible). When presented with other objects that were untrained members of the two classes, two of the three chimpanzees labeled the new items correctly. Although it is possible that perceptual aspects of the two sets of objects aided in their categorization (see section on perceptual classes), it is also possible that functional aspects of the objects were used to classify them (i.e., as edible and inedible; see also Bovet & Vauclair, 1998, 2001). Functional classes may also be related to relational classes in the sense that a relationship among the trained objects in a class must be extracted to be able to correctly label the novel objects. 2.5. Summary The experiments described in this section suggest that many-to-one matching training results in the development of emergent relations between samples associated with a common comparison that can be described as functional equivalences. Perhaps the most convincing evidence of these functional equivalences comes from the results of transfer of training procedures in which, following many-to-one matching training and the reassignment of one pair of the original samples to new comparisons, emergent relations can be shown to have developed between the remaining samples and the new comparison stimuli. Further research has indicated that the nature of the functional equivalence is likely to be the common representation of the two samples that were associated with the same comparison. There is also evidence that functional equivalences are not unique to the many-to-one matching procedure. Functional equivalences have been found following symmetry training and following Vaughan’s (1988) multiple-reversal procedure. Thus, the development of associative classes is a robust and general phenomenon in the nonhuman animal literature. Furthermore, associative classes comprising large numbers of exemplars have been found with this procedure. Formal equivalence – a special case of emergent stimulus relations involving reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity – appears to be difficult to demonstrate in pigeons, but this failure may result from the strong directionality of stimulus relations produced by the specific procedures used rather than by a conceptual deficit in the animals. Similarly, learning by exclusion – a conceptual ability that can be found relatively easily in humans (see Dixon, 1977) – thus far also appears to be somewhat limited in nonhuman animals. Finally, the learning of functional classes, which allows novel objects to be sorted according to their function rather than their perceptual features, has so far only been documented in baboons and apes. Although humans have perfected the application of associative concepts in their use of language to refer to objects not currently present, the capacity to show emergent (untrained) associations, an all important property of human language, appears to be present in nonhuman animals as well. 3. Relational Classes Relational classes, like associative classes, do not depend on the absolute perceptual properties of stimuli. In fact, individual stimuli cannot be assigned to a relational class because such classes depend on the relationship among stimuli; they thus require stimulus comparison. Examples of relational classes are: larger than, brighter than, heavier than, and better (or more reinforcing) than. Thus, a single stimulus can belong to one class (better than) if the stimulus to which it is being compared is worse, while that same stimulus can belong to another class (worse than) if the stimulus to which it is being compared is better. A potential problem in interpreting the results of experiments examining the formation of relational classes is that relational responding to stimuli lying along a continuum (e.g., better than or larger than) may be explained in terms of the generalization of absolute associative values of those stimuli. According to Spence (1937), when one trains a simple discrimination involving two values along one of these dimensions, the absolute stimulus generalization gradients that form around the training stimuli should sum algebraically to produce a net stimulus generalization gradient that has its peak at a value that is displaced from the S+ in the direction away from the S-. For this reason, any test involving stimuli that are not too far removed from the S+ or the S- may produce what can be interpreted as relational responding, so-called transposition. This associative account is problematic for the development of a relational class, because the generalization of absolute values may provide a more parsimonious interpretation of such responding than a relational interpretation (see Lazareva, Wasserman, & Young, 2005 for a critical discussion of these issues and new data which challenge Spence’s classical account). 3.1. Transitive Inference One way to contend with the problem of differential absolute value is to use stimuli that can be described in purely relational terms, as is the case with the transitive inference effect. In its simplest form, transitive inference can be described as the presentation of two propositions (e.g., A is better than B and B is better than C) from which an inference can be made (i.e., A is better than C). Transitive responding provides evidence for the development of emergent relations among stimuli and has been used to assess the age at which children are able to reason (Piaget, 1928). Bryant and Trabasso (1971) helped to refine the transitive inference procedure by expanding the task to five terms (to avoid end-point effects as in the above example, where A is always better and C is never better). More importantly, Bryant and Trabasso developed a nonverbal version of the task, in which four discriminations are trained (A+B-, B+C-, C+D-, D+E-) and transitive responding is demonstrated on BD test trials when B is selected over D. More recently, this version of the task has been used to document transitive responding in several different species including rats (Davis, 1992; Roberts & Phelps, 1994), pigeons (Fersen, Wynne, Delius, & Staddon, 1991; Steirn, Weaver, & Zentall, 1995; Lazareva & Wasserman, 2006), crows (Lazareva, Smirnova, Bagozkaja, Zorina, Rayevsky, & Wasserman, 2004), monkeys (McGonigle & Chalmers, 1977), and chimpanzees (Boysen, Berntson, Shreyer, & Quigley, 1993; Gillan, 1981). Although some authors have proposed that transitive responding can be explained by simpler conditioning processes, such as the specific reinforcement histories associated with the test stimuli (Couvillon & Bitterman, 1992; Wynne, 1997; Siemann & Delius, 1998) or to differential value transfer from the positive stimuli with which the test stimuli were paired during training (Fersen et al., 1991), recent evidence suggests that such emergent responding can be found even when these simpler processes are largely ruled out (Roberts & Phelps, 1994; Weaver, Steirn, & Zentall, 1997; Lazareva et al., 2004; Lazareva & Wasserman, 2006). There has been some speculation that transitive inference allows animals to learn their place in dominance hierarchies without the risks involved in learning their dominance status relative to every member of the group. Instead, an animal can learn its dominance status relative to a few animals whose rank is similar to its own and then, through observation, learn the dominance rank of the other animals, relative to those animals whose rank is already known. Recent research suggests that such dominance hierarchies can be acquired through observation by pinyon jays (Pas-y-Miño, Bond, Kamil, & Balda, 2004), hens (Hogue, Beaugrand, & Lague, 1996) and even fish (Grosenik, Clement, & Fernal, 2007). Although transitive inference may aid in the acquisition of dominance hierarchies, it seems unlikely that the efficient development of dominance hierarchies is responsible for the arbitrary form of transitive inference that has been found in nonsocial tasks. 3.2. Same/Different Learning Another kind of relational class that does not suffer from an absolute learning account is same/different. A pair of stimuli is judged to be the same if they are identical and judged to be different if they are nonidentical, without regard to the properties of the individual stimuli. Of course, merely training animals to sort pairs of stimuli according to whether they do or do not appear to be the same is not sufficient evidence that the animals have the capacity to make same/different judgments, because the animals may simply have learned to sort the particular training stimuli according to their absolute properties. What is needed is evidence that the identity relation controls comparison choice; this evidence comes from generalization tests with novel stimuli. In an early study of same/different discrimination learning, Zentall and Hogan (1976) found that, if pigeons were trained to choose the same shape as the sample, they then showed better transfer of that training to new stimuli which differed in color than did pigeons that were originally trained to choose a shape which was different from the sample. Unfortunately, pigeons tend to be neophobic and the presentation of novel stimuli appears to interfere with immediate transfer of matching. To overcome this problem, Zentall, Edwards, Moore, and Hogan (1981) used an alternative strategy; their procedure involved training on matching-to-sample and oddity-from-sample with four different hues as samples. Each sample hue was experienced with two of the three remaining hues as the nonmatching comparison. On test trials, the remaining hue replaced either the matching or the nonmatching comparison and choice accuracy was assessed. For pigeons trained on matching, the results were straightforward. Replacing the correct (or matching) comparison resulted in a large decrease in choice accuracy, whereas replacing the incorrect (or nonmatching) comparison resulted in no decrease in choice accuracy. But, for pigeons trained on oddity, the results were surprising. Replacing the correct (or nonmatching) comparison resulted in little decrease in choice accuracy, whereas replacing the incorrect (or matching) comparison led to a large decrease in choice accuracy (see Figure 6). Thus, in spite of the fact that these pigeons had both the sample and the correct comparison present, the absence of the incorrect (matching) comparison prevented good transfer. On the other hand, the presence of the incorrect (matching) comparison was sufficient to promote good transfer. For both groups, acquisition appeared to be based on the presence of the comparison that matched the sample; but, once it was identified, pigeons in the matching condition chose it, whereas pigeons in the oddity condition chose the alternative comparison. In recent years, studies of both birds and mammals have revealed even better evidence for the transfer of conceptual same/different discriminations (e.g., Blaisdell & Cook, 2005; Katz, Wright, & Bachevalier, 2002; Mercado, Killebrew, Pack, Macha, & Herman, 2000; Oden, Thompson & Premack, 1988; Pepperberg, 1987; Wright, Cook, Rivera, Sands, & Delius, 1988; see Wasserman, Young, & Cook, 2004 and Wright & Katz, 2006 for reviews). These more recent experiments have shown that experience with several examples of same/different relations increases the tendency of pigeons and both old- and new-world monkeys to transfer that training to new stimuli (Katz, Wright, & Bachevalier, 2002; Wright et al., 1988; Wright, Rivera, Katz & Bachevalier, 2003). However, no such constraint or limitation of stimulus set size seems to hold for chimpanzees (Oden, Thompson, & Premack, 1988).
3.2.1. Same/Different learning using multiple-item displays: Effect of entropy Investigations of pigeons and baboons by Wasserman, Young, Fagot and their colleagues have used as discriminative stimuli arrays of black-and-white computer icons that were either all the same as or all different from one another (see Figure 7 for arrays). In one example (Wasserman et al., 1995; Young & Wasserman, 1997, Experiment 1), pigeons were first taught to peck one button when they viewed an array that comprised 16 copies of the same icon and to peck a second button when they viewed an array that comprised one copy of 16 different icons (a same-different discrimination task). These same and different training displays were created from one set of 16 computer icons. The pigeons were later tested with new same and new different displays that were created from a second set of 16 computer icons that had never before been shown during discrimination training. Accuracy to the training stimuli averaged from 83% to 93% correct and accuracy to the testing stimuli averaged from 71% to 79% correct; in each case, choice accuracy reliably exceeded the chance score of 50% correct. Such robust discrimination learning and stimulus generalization attest to the pigeon’s acquisition of an abstract same-different concept (for more on the nature of this concept, see Wasserman, Young, & Nolan, 2000; Young & Wasserman, 1997; Young, Wasserman, & Dalrymple, 1997; Young, et al., 1997). Should these results be taken at face value? Perhaps not. The authors decided to see what effect, if any, the number of icons had on the pigeon’s same-different discrimination. They began training the pigeons that had successfully learned and transferred the 16-icon same-different discrimination with displays of 12, 8, 4, and 2 icons. The result was unexpected failure. The pigeons stopped pecking after only 1 or 2 days of training. This cessation of responding was not random; the birds stopped responding on 2-icon different trials. Prior to this stoppage, the pigeons repeatedly pecked the “same” report key despite the presentation of 2 different icons. The authors pondered this result for some time; but, they could make no sense of it. So, they decided to change direction and to see how pigeons would respond to displays that comprised a mixture of same and different icons. This issue was of interest in its own right, but the authors had no idea that the results of such same/different mixtures would help them understand the pigeon’s peculiar performance with small numbers of icons. The same arrays and the different arrays in these experiments really represent the endpoints of a scale of variability. The same displays entail minimal variability, with all 16 icons the same as one another, whereas the different displays entail maximal variability, with all 16 icons different from one another. So, the authors explored pigeons’ response to intermediate degrees of variability (Young & Wasserman, 1997, Experiment 2). They constructed three mixture arrays: 2 icons each repeated 8 times (2 icons x 8 copies), 4 icons each repeated 4 times (4 icons x 4 copies), and 8 icons each repeated twice (8 icons x 2 copies). These mixtures were presented as rare probe tests and food reinforcement was given after all of the pigeons’ report responses. It was not obvious how the pigeons would respond to these mixture displays. All three mixtures included more than one kind of icon, perhaps prompting the pigeons to make a “different” response; but, all three mixtures also included repetitions of icons, which might prompt the pigeons to make a “same” response. It was also possible that the pigeons would show a graded change in responding as the displays went from being all same (1 icon x 16 copies) to all different (16 icons x 1 copy), thus disclosing a sensitivity to differing degrees of display variability. In fact, the pigeons exhibited a smooth transition in their responding as the mixture arrays changed from 16 icons x 1 copy (different) to 8 icons x 2 copies to 4 icons x 4 copies to 2 icons x 8 copies to 1 icon x 16 copies (same), suggesting some form of dimensional stimulus control. Over a half century ago, Shannon and Weaver (1949) quantified the amount of variety or diversity in a categorical variable by a weighted average of the number of bits of information that are required to predict each of the categories of the variable. That score – entropy – nicely fit the pigeons’ response to same/different mixtures (Young & Wasserman, 1997). It also suggested a way to understand why the number of items had such a strong effect on pigeons’ behavior. To first gain more quantitative information about the effect of the number of items on discrimination behavior, Young, Wasserman, and Garner (1997, Experiment 1) trained pigeons on 16-item displays and later tested the pigeons with displays containing fewer items. Birds were given nondifferentially reinforced testing displays comprising 2, 4, 8, 12, or 14 items that were either the same as or different from one another. The use of nondifferential reinforcement meant that the extinction of responding that was earlier observed under differential reinforcement would not now affect testing performance. Discrimination of 16-icon same from different training arrays averaged 89% correct. Discrimination of same from different 2-, 4-, 8-, 12-, and 14-icon testing arrays averaged 49%, 54%, 73%, 79%, and 83% correct, respectively. More detailed examination of choice behavior disclosed that the decline in performance with smaller arrays was due to an increase in errors to the different arrays. The probability of choosing “different” did not vary across the six same trial array sizes, but it did vary across the six different trial array sizes; the fewer the icons, the lower the probability of choosing “different.” In fact, the pigeons strongly reported “same” to the 2- and 4-icon different displays. Why? When pigeons are trained to discriminate 16-icon same arrays from 16-icon different arrays, they may actually have learned to make one response to displays with an entropy of 0.0 and another response to displays with an entropy of 4.0. During testing, a bird might distribute its responses to novel arrays as a function of their entropy; displays with entropies closer to 0.0 should be classified as “same,” whereas those with entropies closer to 4.0 should be classified as “different.” The entropy of a 2-item different display, 1.0, is more similar to that of 16-item same displays, 0.0, than it is to that of 16-item different displays, 4.0. Thus, this entropy discrimination should prompt classification of 2-item different displays as “same” rather than as “different,” in accord with earlier findings. These results thus represent an important and counterintuitive confirmation of pigeons’ use of entropy in classifying complex visual displays. The next step was to learn more about the comparative generality of these pigeon results. So, the authors explored the extent to which a nonhuman primate’s same-different discrimination behavior resembled that of pigeons. They were not only interested in whether primates can learn a same-different concept (prior evidence suggests that they can, e.g., Wright et al., 1983), but they were also interested in whether the nature of that concept learning is categorical or dimensional. Wasserman, Fagot, and Young (2001) thus trained and tested baboons with the same experimental stimuli as previously used with pigeons. Experiment 1 found close correspondence between baboons and pigeons in their discriminative responding to familiar and novel arrays of same and different items: (a) baboons quickly learned to discriminate same from different stimulus arrays that comprised 16 icons and (b) baboons effectively generalized that same-different discrimination to arrays of novel icons. Accuracy to the training stimuli averaged 91% correct and accuracy to the testing stimuli averaged 81% correct; in each case, choice accuracy reliably exceeded the chance score of 50% correct. Experiments 2 and 3 showed close correspondence between baboons’ and pigeons’ responses to mixed arrays that comprised both same and different icons: the baboons exhibited graded responding that accorded with display variability. The authors (Wasserman, Young, & Fagot, 2001) later varied the number of icons in the arrays to see if baboons’ behavior would be affected by this manipulation. Decreasing the number of icons from the training value of 16 had a large decremental impact on baboon’s discrimination of same from different displays, as had been true of pigeons (Young et al., 1997). 3.2.2. Same/Different learning using multiple-item displays in humans The fact that such widely different species as pigeons and baboons responded so similarly to familiar and to novel same and different displays as well as the fact that these two species responded so similarly to mixed displays of same and different items and to reductions in the number of displayed items strongly suggests that these results may have broad applicability to other animals given similar discrimination training and generalization testing tasks. Yet, these results with pigeons and baboons struck the authors as most peculiar from the vantage point of human judgment. Surely, humans would not respond as had pigeons and baboons. If humans were given mixtures of same and different icons, then one would certainly expect them to respond “different” so long as any of the items differed from one another. And, varying the number of icons should certainly have no measurable effect on performance; after all, two different items are just as different from one another as are eight different items. With no available data on the question, the authors conducted a project with college students to parallel the research that they had completed with pigeons and baboons. Young and Wasserman (2001, Experiment 1) first taught college students to discriminate same from different arrays. Students were told that they would be viewing a series of arrays and attempting to learn which response was correct for each. Students were to make their best guess as to which of two responses was correct; they were then given feedback in the form of a tone (correct) or a flash of the screen (incorrect). For half of the participants, the “1” key of a computer keyboard was correct for same arrays and the “3” key was correct for different arrays. For the other half of the participants, the keys assignments were reversed. The goal of the student participants was to predict the correct response for each array. The words “same” or “different” were never used in the instructions. The authors then tested the students with displays of intermediate variability and with displays comprising fewer icons. Students’ responding to the testing arrays that contained fewer than 16 icons or that were mixtures of same and different icons revealed disparate behavioral profiles. To separate the disparate profiles, the authors performed a hierarchical cluster analysis of responding to the different arrays and focused on the highest-level two-cluster division: 80% of the students were in one cluster and 20% were in the other. The authors used only the different arrays in their cluster analysis to determine whether disparities in responding to those arrays would predict disparities in responding to the mixture arrays. Students in the smaller (Continuous) cluster responded in accord with the use of entropy; they were more likely to choose “same” to the different arrays as the number of icons was reduced, but they consistently chose “same” to the same arrays regardless of icon number. The Continuous students also exhibited a strong sensitivity to the full range of display variability to the mixture arrays; as the mixture was changed from mostly same to mostly different icons, responding changed from mostly “same” to mostly “different.” So, people in the Continuous cluster responded as if display variability were measured along a continuous scale, just like pigeons and baboons. Students in the larger (Categorical) cluster behaved quite differently, treating the discrimination more categorically; they were largely unaffected by the number of icons in the same and different displays. Plus, these students nearly always made a “different” response to all of the mixtures (although there was a modest effect of the composition of the mixtures); when any of the icons were different, they tended to choose “different;” only when all of the icons were identical did they consistently choose “same.” None of the individual difference characteristics that were examined (handedness, American College Test scores, sex, grade point average, or age) accounted for the disparate behavioral profiles among the students. These data suggest that the continuous response profile is not unique to nonhuman animals; some humans also exhibit this pattern. But, most humans and, so far, no nonhumans have exhibited the categorical response profile. Perhaps only language-experienced apes and humans will respond with the categorical profile. The fact that some humans exhibit the continuous response profile may indicate that these individuals do not deploy language in performing the same-different discrimination. How might language participate in these two disparate patterns of same-different discrimination performance? One possibility is that having specific symbols for “same” and “different” may effectively transform a discrimination that is mediated by variability or entropy into one that is leveraged by linguistic categorical labeling (for discussions of labeling effects on conceptual classification by nonhuman animals, see, for example: de Rose, 1996; Horne & Lowe, 1996; Stromer & MacKay, 1996). Another possibility is that this dramatic disparity between the dichotomization and the dimensionalization of same and different stimulus arrays is more apparent than real. All organisms may scale the stimuli in terms of entropy, but their same-different decisions may arise from setting different thresholds. Subjects that appear to be dichotomizing the stimuli may place their decision threshold near an entropy value of 0.0, whereas subjects that appear to be dimensionalizing the stimuli may place their decision threshold near the midpoint of the entropy range. 3.3 Summary Evidence for the development of relational concepts comes from transitive inference performance and same/different learning. Although the mechanism responsible for transitive inference performance is not well understood, evidence from several studies suggests that it cannot be attributed to simpler conditioning processes such as the specific reinforcement histories associated with the test stimuli or to differential value transfer from the positive stimuli with which the test stimuli were paired during training. In the case of same/different discrimination learning involving a single sample stimulus and a choice of two comparison stimuli, transfer to novel stimuli has been spontaneous in the case of chimpanzees, and, in the case of monkeys and pigeons, is typically facilitated by large training stimulus set sizes. There is also evidence that the novelty of the transfer stimuli may obscure better transfer effects in pigeons. When same/different discrimination learning has been studied with multiple-item displays in pigeons and baboons, good evidence of transfer has been found. Later results suggest that the entropy of the display may play an important role in such discrimination learning and transfer. This hypothesis is supported by the finding that pigeons and monkeys responded to displays containing some same and some different items proportionally, rather than all or none. In contrast, most (but not all) humans responded to the intermediate displays as “different.” These humans may be using linguistic categorical labeling rather than entropy as the basis of their discrimination, although it is also possible that they have merely set their threshold for responding “same” at a point different from that of pigeons and monkeys. 4. Relations Between Relations The research discussed thus far provides convincing evidence that nonhuman animals can discriminate objects and events on the basis of their shared perceptual, associative, and relational properties. But, can the pigeon or any other nonhuman animal acquire a higher-order relational concept like an analogy? For some theorists, the production and comprehension of analogies are hallmarks of human reasoning that hinge on sophisticated linguistic or representational competence (e.g., French, 1995; Gentner, 1998; Gentner, Holyoak, & Kokinov, 2001; Holyoak, 1984; Holyoak & Thagard, 1997; Sternberg, 1977). If so, then one might well despair of interrogating a prelinguistic human or a nonlinguistic animal about analogy. Nevertheless, as described below, comparative and developmental psychologists may now have several available means to query their respective nonlinguistic and prelinguistic subjects for evidence of their capacity to implicitly recognize and then explicitly judge, complete, and/or construct analogies. 4.1. Analogical or Relational Matching-to-Sample In the analogical or relational matching-to-sample task, the animal is required to match a sample set (either two or more identical items on some trials and two or more nonidentical items on other trials) to a different distinctive set of identical or nonidentical items. Successful matching implies that the animal judges that the relation (identity or nonidentity) instantiated by one of the choice sets is the same relation as the relation (identity or nonidentity) instantiated by the sample set. This task is essentially a nonlinguistic analogy problem in which all of the arguments are visually provided. Critically, success on the analogical matching task requires the animal to attend to the higher-order relations (same or different) between relations (identity or nonidentity) because none of the items in the sample set is presented in either of the two choice sets. When each same or each different stimulus display consists of a single pair of items, the results point to what David Premack labeled a ‘profound disparity’ between the analogical capacities of humans and apes on the one hand, and other animals on the other (Premack, 1978, 1983; Thompson & Oden, 1996). Specifically (see Sections 4.3 and 4.4), no nonhuman animal other than chimpanzees with a history of symbol training has provided unequivocal evidence of its ability to categorically match a pair of sample items (e.g., a pair of padlocks) with another distinctive pair of identical objects (e.g., a pair of cups) and to match a pair of nonidentical objects (e.g., a pencil and eraser) with another pair of nonidentical objects (e.g., a shoe and ball). 4.2. Relational Matching by Pigeons and Baboons Interestingly, the ‘profound disparity’ does not appear to hold for either pigeons or baboons when each sample and comparison ‘same/different’ stimulus display in the relational matching task consists of a large number of stimuli (e.g., 16) (Cook & Wasserman, in press; Fagot, Wasserman, & Young, 2001). Consider the task that is schematized in Figure 7. Here, an animal is shown a sample display that depicts items that are either all the same as one another or all different from one another. After presentation of the sample display, two choice displays are shown: the first of all same items and the second of all different items. The correct response is to select the choice display that involves the same relation among the items as was illustrated in the sample display. Critically, none of the icons that were shown in the sample display are shown in either of the choice displays. So, only the relations among the items in the sample and choice displays can guide discriminative responding; the particular items themselves are of no importance.
Cook and Wasserman (in press) gave this same-different relational matching task to pigeons to see if they could successfully solve the task and generalize their matching-to-sample behavior to sample displays that contained novel visual icons. Successful generalization to novel sample displays would provide clear evidence that these birds had indeed learned a highly abstract and broadly applicable concept. Cook and Wasserman (in press) found just such successful discrimination learning based on the relation between relations with 4 x 4 grids of 16 same and different stimulus arrays drawn from five distinctive sets of colored icons. Successful transfer performance in conditions where the alignment, orientation, and size of the icons were varied and mixed provided further evidence that the birds’ choices were based on their perception of abstract higher-order relations. The effect of the number of icons in the stimulus arrays on the birds’ performance was not tested in the Cook and Wasserman (in press) study, but given the results from previous studies by Wasserman and his colleagues with both pigeons and baboons, it seems reasonable to believe that stimulus variability or entropy played a critical part in the pigeons’ discrimination behavior (cf., Wasserman, Fagot, & Young, 2001; Young & Wasserman, 1997; Young, Wasserman, & Garner, 1997). Indeed, in an earlier study, Fagot, Wasserman, and Young (2001) gave the same-different relational matching task with multiple icon arrays to baboons. The researchers reported that their baboons – like the pigeons in Cook and Wasserman’s (in press) subsequent study – successfully matched 16-item arrays of identical icons or nonidentical icons with the corresponding comparison array instantiating the same relation. Their work then proceeded to more deeply explore the cognitive basis of this relational matching behavior. Follow-up research investigated: (a) the effects of the number of items in a sample (and a test) display and (b) the effects of mixtures of same and different items in a sample display on relational matching-to-sample behavior. That research suggested that the baboons were strongly controlled by the variability of the items that were shown in the sample stimulus displays. Because their methods were then novel, for comparative purposes, Fagot et al. (2001) trained and tested humans on the same discrimination. This comparison disclosed both commonalities and disparities in the cognitive processes of abstract conceptual behavior. Baboons and humans both learned relational matching-to-sample. However, humans learned far faster than baboons and their final level of discriminative performance was much higher. Baboons and humans both transferred relational matching-to-sample to novel sample stimuli. But, only baboons showed a generalization decrement to the novel testing samples; humans responded with equivalent accuracy to the training and testing samples. Baboons and humans both showed a worsening of relational matching-to-sample performance when the number of sample icons was reduced from 16 to 12 to 8 to 4 to 2. But, only baboons exhibited a strong tendency to report “same” to different sample displays that contained 2 or 4 icons; humans’ discrimination was much more mildly and symmetrically affected by reductions in the number of sample icons. Baboons and humans both were strongly controlled by the entropy of sample displays that contained various mixtures of same icons and different icons. But, humans more abruptly and completely reported “different” to mixture sample arrays with an entropy value of 1.0 or more. The results from the relational matching studies with pigeons and baboons unequivocally show that these animals can ignore surface similarities and match the sample and testing arrays according to the abstract relations between them. As was also true in earlier research (e.g., Wasserman et al., 2001; Young & Wasserman 2001), neither baboons nor pigeons exhibited the strong categorical behavior that was evidenced by humans trained and tested under comparable circumstances. Nevertheless, it is clear that variability or entropy provides sufficient information for nonhuman animals (and perhaps humans as well) to make both first-order and second-order relational discriminations. 4.3. Categorical Relational Matching by Nonhuman Primates and Children In contrast to baboons and pigeons, Sarah, a chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes) proved to be adept at categorical analogical matching-to-sample when only two items were shown in the sample and testing alternatives (see Section 4.4 for more details). Premack (1978, 1983) suspected that prior “language-training” provided Sarah with the necessary cognitive scaffolding to judge the equivalence of analogical relations. Results from studies of physical and conceptual/analogical matching tasks by chimpanzees, either with or without prior experience using representational symbols for the relations of same and different, support this hypothesis. Would other chimpanzees fare as well as Sarah? Spontaneous analogical matching of relations between relations by chimpanzees, under conditions of nondifferential reinforcement, was reported by Thompson, Oden, and Boysen (1997). One of the animals in the study was Sarah, whose analogical capacities have already been described. The three remaining animals had not experienced language training per se, but they did have a history of conditional and numeric token training (Boysen, 1993; Boysen & Berntson, 1989); perhaps importantly, prior to the matching study, they had been trained with symbols for the relations “same” and “different.” Specifically, the chimpanzees were rewarded for choosing a heart-shaped symbol presented on a touch screen after being shown a pair of identical objects or their pictorial representations (i.e., if AA, then ♥ = S+); when presented with a pair of nonidentical objects, the chimpanzees were rewarded for choosing a diagonal form on the touch screen (i.e., if QM, then / = S+). This conditional discriminative performance transferred to novel objects and pictures. Later, and in the absence of the symbols, the same animals were tested on a series of physical and analogical matching problems. Correct choices on physical matching trials were differentially rewarded, whereas correct analogical matches were nondifferentially rewarded (i.e., all choices were reinforced). The chimpanzees’ overall performances on the physical matching problems were well above chance (i.e., 83.6% to 87.5%). Moreover, all three animals spontaneously matched the analogical relations and their overall performance levels (i.e., 80.1% to 87.5% correct) were equivalent to those of Sarah. As in Sarah’s case, there was no evidence that perceptual or associative factors mediated the chimpanzees’ analogical matching behaviors (Thompson et al., 1997). In another study, infant chimpanzees lacking any experience with a symbolic token system were presented with matching-to-sample tasks. After first being trained to match with only a lock and a cup, these chimpanzees successfully matched a variety of novel objects on the very first testing trial (Oden, Thompson, & Premack, 1988). Despite this evidence of their having acquired a broadly and spontaneously construed matching concept, these same chimpanzees nevertheless failed throughout a variety of training conditions to match pairs of objects on the basis of their analogical relatedness of identity (e.g., a pair of locks matches a pair of cups, but not a paired eraser and ball) or nonidentity (e.g., a paired clock and shoe matches a paired eraser and ball, but not a pair of cups). In this regard, the performance of these chimpanzees did not differ from what Premack had reported previously for language-naïve chimpanzees. Thompson and his colleagues (Thompson et al., 1997; Thompson & Oden, 2000) suggested that the results from symbol-sophisticated and symbol-naïve chimpanzees support the hypothesis that prior experience with symbols for relations per se is sufficient for chimpanzees to immediately match higher-order analogical relations between relations (cf., Premack, 1988; Smith, King, Witt, & Rickel, 1975). Providing concrete tokens to represent abstract same/different relations perhaps permits the covert recoding of the abstract (i.e., propositional) relations as imaginal representations of the tokens, thereby reducing the analogical matching task to one that is functionally equivalent to a physical same/different matching task. 4.3.1. Do labels affect children’s use of analogical similarity? The previous discussion of Sarah and the other symbol-trained chimpanzees highlights the powerful catalytic effects of symbolic labels. If we are to group humans with chimpanzees, then presumably human children might likewise be affected by the presence of labels. Evidence indicating that is the case was reported by Rattermann and her colleagues (Rattermann & Gentner, 1998; Thompson, Rattermann, & Oden, 2001). Results from one such study which examined children’s analogical reasoning abilities suggest that the presence of labels is a powerful catalyst for the use of relational similarity. Rattermann and Gentner (1998) found that, without relational labels, the performance of 3-year-olds was comparable to that of non-token trained chimpanzees. The researchers also found that older children (5-year-olds) were quite adept at an explicit analogical reasoning task, much like Sarah and the other symbol-trained chimpanzees. Interestingly, the presence of a set of simple labels improved the performance of the 3-year-olds to a level comparable to that of the 5-year-olds—an improvement in performance akin to that found in label/token-trained versus non-label/token-trained chimpanzees. Rattermann and Gentner (1998) used an explicit analogical reasoning task that pitted perceptual sameness against analogical sameness. Using a technique called cross-mapping, 3-, 4-, and 5-year-olds were shown two triads of objects, each arranged in monotonically decreasing size (e.g., 4 3 2 —> 3 2 1) in a fan-like pattern. One set belonged to the experimenter and one set belonged to the child. The child watched the experimenter place a sticker under an object in her set and then searched in his own set for a sticker hidden under the corresponding object. Because of the cross-mapping, matches based on perceptual sameness (e.g., 3 —> 3) competed against matches based on analogical sameness (e.g., 3 —> 2). To further examine the effects of perceptual sameness, Rattermann and Gentner (1998) manipulated the “richness” of the objects forming the triads; for half the children the triads were formed with simple, sparse objects which minimized perceptual sameness, whereas for the other children the triads were formed with rich, complex objects that enhanced perceptual sameness. The child received feedback for the correct answer, which was always based on analogical sameness. The results showed both a strong developmental change and an effect of object complexity: 3-year-olds produced 54% relational responses with the sparse stimuli and 32% with the rich stimuli, whereas 5-year-olds produced 95% relational responses with the sparse stimuli and 68% with the rich stimuli. To examine the effects of labels on young children’s use of analogical sameness, Rattermann and Gentner (1998) taught a group of 3-year-olds to use the relational labels “Daddy/Mommy/Baby,” which conveyed the relation of monotonic change in, for example, a ‘family’ set of teddy bears or toy penguins. When the labels were used on each trial, 3-year-olds were 84% correct, performing comparably to the 5-year-olds in the original task. The beneficial effects of learning relational labels were not dependent on direct modeling. After experience with the “Daddy/Mommy/Baby” labels, 3-year-olds maintained much of their gain (57%) when they were given new stimuli on which no labels were used. Indeed, 3-year-olds who returned 4 to 8 weeks after the initial session produced significantly more correct relational responses (62%) than a control group without label experience (28%). These experiments thus demonstrate that language (symbolic labeling) can facilitate relational representation in young children and that it does so, as suggested, by “providing an invitation to form comparisons and further, to provide an index for stable memory encoding of the newly represented relational structure (Rattermann & Gentner, 1998, p. 280). 4.3.2. Do labels affect categorical analogical equivalence judgments by monkeys? Might explicit training with conditional cues symbolizing relational sameness and difference catalyze the ability of monkeys to detect and to judge the categorical equivalence of analogical relations as it had for children and chimpanzees? Results from a pilot experiment and extensive follow-up study suggest not (Washburn, Thompson & Oden, 1997; Thompson, Oden, & Washburn, in preparation). Similar to the chimpanzees in the study of analogical matching, the test-sophisticated macaque monkeys in these experiments were trained to use a joystick to move a cursor to a circle stimulus displayed on a computer monitor following their exposure to a pair of computer-generated stimuli, provided they instantiated an ‘identity’ relation (e.g., if AA, then —> O = S+). Choice of an alternative triangle cue was correct following presentations of a pair of stimuli instantiating a nonidentity relation (e.g., if CD, then —> ? = S+). The monkeys then transferred their performance to novel exemplars of the identity and nonidentity relations. Subsequently, however, as shown in Figure 8, the monkeys’ analogical matching performances, unlike those of the chimpanzees, remained at chance levels in the absence of the conditional O and ? cues. Nevertheless, there was no difference in the ability of monkeys or chimpanzees to match items on the basis of their physical features (i.e., color, shape, and size).
How might one account for the success of the monkeys in generalizing the initial conditional discrimination between identity pairs and the O cue, on the one hand, and that between nonidentity stimulus pairs and the ? cue, on the other? One possibility is that choice of the O and p cues was a function of the matching or nonmatching outcome of a computational operation performed on individual within-pair items rather than on the perception of relational identity or nonidentity (Thompson & Oden, 2000; Thompson, Oden, & Washburn, in preparation). Application of matching and nonmatching operators is likely to occur in all nonhuman primates, as well as in mammals and birds (cf., Thompson, 1995; Thompson & Oden, 2000). How might one account for these disparities in performance across species and between tasks? As described below, both adult and infant macaque monkeys, contrary to chimpanzees and children, appear to be perceptually insensitive to relational equivalencies as measured in implicit detection tests (see Thompson & Oden, 1996, 2000). Hence, presumably the O and ▲ cues could not acquire symbolic referential meaning for the relations same and different as hypothesized for children and chimpanzees. 4.3.3. Implicit or tacit detection of analogical relations by children and chimpanzees Karl Lashley (1929) claimed that, “The use of symbols depends upon the recognition of similarity and not the reverse.” As described below, there are good reasons from studies of children, chimpanzees, and monkeys to accept his claim. Evidence for the differential capacities of human and chimpanzee infants, as well as adult and infant rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta), to implicitly or tacitly detect analogical relations without experimenter direction comes from studies measuring either visual gaze or object handling in preference-for-novelty tasks. Tyrrell, Stauffer, and Snowman (1991) presented 7-month-old human infants with a preference-for-novelty task in order to test their ability to tacitly detect analogical similarity. Infants were first familiarized with a pair of objects that instantiated either the relation of same (AA) or the relation of different (BC) depending on the experimental condition. After this familiarization trial, infants were presented with two novel object pairs, instantiating same and different relations, DD and EF, respectively. Using gaze duration as their dependent measure, Tyrrell et al. found that the infants looked significantly longer at the objects instantiating the relationship that was novel compared to that relationship with which they had been familiarized on the first trial; so, following familiarization to an identity pair (AA), the infants looked longer at EF than at DD on the test trial. From this evidence, Tyrrell et al. concluded that infants as young as 7-months of age can spontaneously detect same and different relations. The finding was important if only because it seemed counterintuitive given that children cannot reliably make analogical equivalence judgments until they are 3 to 5 years of age or older (cf., House, Brown, & Scott, 1974; Piaget, Montangero, & Billeter, 1977; Tyrrell, Zingaro, & Minard, 1993). Prior to the Tyrrell et al. (1991) study, Oden, Thompson, and Premack (1990) had reported that measures of object handling time in a preference-for-novelty study with infant chimpanzees pointed to a disparity between an organism’s capacities to implicitly or tacitly detect relational sameness and difference as opposed to its capacity to explicitly judge analogical equivalence relations. The animals in this study were the same four “language-naïve” chimpanzees that had consistently failed to match analogical relations instantiated by pairs of objects, despite the evidence of their possessing a broadly construed matching concept based on physical identity (Oden, et al., 1988). On the implicit (i.e., uninformed) preference-for-novelty task, these same animals handled an object for a shorter time if, on a prior familiarization trial, they had handled the same object than if they had handled a different object. This finding is consistent with that obtained in the physical matching task. But, in contrast to their failure to match analogical relations, measures of differential handling times by these same animals indicated that they tacitly detected the relational sameness or difference between pairs of objects. The chimpanzees handled a pair of objects longer if it instantiated a novel same/different relation rather than a familiar same/different relation. So, why did these young chimpanzees fail to categorically match analogical relations? Perhaps they lacked requisite exposure to the presumed facilitative effects of symbol training and labeling on the relational recoding that was experienced by other chimpanzees and children (e.g., Rattermann & Gentner, 1998; Thompson et al., 1997). Reviewing the evidence, Thompson and Oden (2000) concluded that, unlike chimpanzees and human children, neither adult nor infant macaque monkeys spontaneously or tacitly detect the equivalence of analogical relations between relations. This disparity across phylogenetic orders of old-world primates held regardless of the behavioral task (preference-for-novelty or habituation/dishabituation) and whether visual gaze or object handling was the dependent measure. What could account for the monkeys’ failure to tacitly detect analogical relations instantiated by pairs of like and unlike stimuli in preference-for-novelty and habituation/dishabituation tasks? Interestingly, there was some evidence from these experiments of longer looking times to stimulus variability; despite their tacit insensitivity to analogical sameness or difference across conditions, the monkeys often looked longer at stimulus pairs instantiated by two nonidentical objects than they looked at stimulus pairs instantiated by two identical objects. That is, two different objects (i.e., reflecting variability) were more interesting than one object repeated (i.e., reflecting no variability). Hence, one possibility for the animals’ failure to tacitly detect analogical sameness and difference with two-item samples may be related to the difficulty to capitalize on their capacity to discriminate entropy differences with stimuli comprising only two items. Recall that Young and Wasserman (2001, Experiment 1) reported that not all humans responded categorically to mixtures of same and different stimulus arrays. Like the response profiles of nonhumans, those of some college students were continuous. If, as suggested in the above discussion, all organisms scale the stimuli in terms of entropy, then perhaps the dichotomy between monkeys and chimpanzees in their relational matching performance with stimulus pairs reflects differences in their respective same/different variability thresholds; the latter chimpanzees--like most humans, but unlike monkeys--may set their decision threshold for entropy near zero. If, as further suggested above, the provision of symbols for “same” and “different” cognitively leverages continuous entropy into categorical judgments, then perhaps combining “entropy infused” stimulus variability with conditional symbol training might provide monkeys with the requisite environmental scaffolding for shifting their thresholds, thereby enabling acquisition of categorical same/different discriminations with stimulus pairs. 4.3.4. Entropy-infused conditional discrimination training with monkeys Flemming and his colleagues recently explored in macaque monkeys the possible synergistic scaffolding effect of combining “entropy infused” stimulus variability (rows of same or different stimuli) with conditional symbol training on the subsequent acquisition of categorical two-alternative same/different discriminations (Flemming, Beran, & Washburn, 2005; Flemming et al., 2007). As had other investigators (Thompson et al., in preparation; Washburn et al., 1997), these researchers first found that their animals failed to discriminate relations between pairs of 2-item stimuli. However, in a subsequent experiment, the same animals rapidly learned to discriminate horizontal 8-element arrays that were all the same from 8-element arrays that were all different. The background color of the display, on which the two rows of icons appeared, served as a conditional cue as to whether the same or the different row was the (randomly determined) S+ on any given trial. Hence, if the background was pink, then the monkeys were rewarded for moving a joystick-controlled cursor to the same array, whereas if the background was black, then they were rewarded for contacting the different array with the cursor. The number of items per row was then reduced in decrements of 2 (i.e., 8 to 6 to 4 to 2). In each case, the monkeys reached a criterion of 80% or better correct in fewer than 50 trials. In the next experiment, the monkeys were tested on an analogical matching task with pairs of same or different icons serving as the sample and choice alternatives. All of the individual icons from which pairs were constructed were physically disparate and, as in the previous experiment, the background color of the display served as the conditional cue signaling whether the correct choice matching the sample relation was same or different. Four of five monkeys reached the 80% or better performance criterion in fewer than 200 trials. These encouraging results suggested that conjoining entropy with symbol training had indeed provided the animals with the requisite environmental scaffolding to shift their discrimination of relational sameness and difference from dimensional to categorical control. In subsequent testing sessions, the conditional cue was present on the first 100 trials and then removed, while the sample and choice stimuli appeared on a white background. Whereas performance with the conditional cue present was always around 95% correct or better, performance dropped immediately to around 55% correct when the conditional cue was not present on a matching trial, and it remained at that level for 300 to 500 within-session trials. Over the course of 6,000 trials of analogical matching without the conditional cue present, none of the monkeys showed any marked improvement in performance. Hence, as in the experiments conducted by Washburn et al. (1997) and Thompson et al. (in preparation), the performance of these old-world monkeys on the analogical matching task deteriorated with the removal of the cognitive scaffolding provided by the symbolic conditional discriminative cue originally conjoined with entropy or its absence. Here, it might be observed that the successful relational matching-to-sample performance of baboons (Fagot et al., 2001) was preceded by extensive prior experience with first-order same-different discrimination training, which entailed distinctive visual symbols representing “same” and “different” report responses (Wasserman et al., 2001). Those symbols and the “same” and “different” report responses were removed during relational matching-to-sample training, but the displays in both first-order and second-order relational training contained 16 visual items. 4.3.5. Summary The evidence reviewed thus far from both human and nonhuman primate studies suggests that entropy can play an important role in the discrimination of relational sameness and difference. However, unlike the case for chimpanzees and children, providing macaque monkeys with concrete tokens or conditional cues to represent analogical relations between relations apparently does not catalyze their ability to make categorical analogical equivalence judgments instantiated by only pairs of like and unlike items (see also, for example, Kuczaj & Hendry, 2003; Savage-Rumbaugh, 1986; Thompson & Oden, 1993). The root of this capacity may be the ability of both chimpanzees and children, but, thus far, not monkeys, to tacitly detect relations between relations instantiated by pairs of items spontaneously and early in life. This tacit perceptual ability precedes the categorical judgment of analogical equivalences. The additional suggestion that the explicit (i.e., judgment) expression of otherwise implicit or tacit perceptual competencies is catalyzed by some form of re-coding via linguistic labeling or concrete symbolic system was independently proposed by Clark and Thornton (1997) in their computational approach to uninformed learning. They found that their artificial intelligent systems ‘ran aground’ in exactly the same class of tasks used with children and nonhuman primates unless their connectionist net was provided with some external means of reducing the search space. Clark and Thornton’s (1997) findings imply that experience using external symbol structures transforms the shape of the computational spaces that must be negotiated in order to solve abstract problems like analogical reasoning. This conclusion implies that analogy requires complex computational processes, consistent with the prevailing views of researchers who study analogical reasoning by humans (e.g., Gentner, 1998; Gentner, Holyoak, & Boikov, 2001; Halford, 1992; Holyoak & Thagard, 1997). 4.4. Formal Analogical Reasoning by Sarah, a Chimpanzee Perhaps the most convincing evidence of formal analogical reasoning by a nonhuman animal in a cognitive manner analogous to that claimed for humans comes from Sarah, a chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes). Early evidence of Sarah’s capacity for making analogical judgments was reflected in her performance on formal analogical problems involving geometric forms and functional relationships between everyday objects (Gillan, Premack, & Woodruff, 1981). Additional evidence of this animal’s capacities for analogical problem solving with geometric forms included not only the completion of partially constructed analogies, but also the spontaneous undirected construction of analogies from geometric elements (Oden, Thompson, & Premack, 2001). In an early set of experiments, Gillan et al. (1981) presented Sarah with four simple geometric forms placed on a display board in a 2 x 2 format (as shown in Figure 9). The two items on the left-hand side instantiated the base relation and the two items on the right-hand side instantiated the target relation, which was either the same as or different from that of the base relation. In either case, physically different geometric forms (i.e., circles vs. squares of various sizes) represented the base and target relations. If the base and target relations were the same (i.e., a correct analogy), then Sarah judged them so by placing the plastic token for the concept ‘same’ from her artificial language between the pairs of forms. If the base and target relations were not the same and hence did not represent a correct analogy, then Sarah judged them so by placing the plastic token for the concept ‘different’ between the pairs of forms (Premack & Premack, 1972; Premack, 1976).
In other experiments, Sarah was presented with a complete base relation on the left-hand side of the display board, but with only one item on the right-hand side. The plastic token for ‘same’ was placed between the base and the incomplete target. Sarah successfully completed the target relation by choosing from two alternative forms the one that produced an analogy. Sarah further demonstrated her capacity in the Gillan et al. (1981) study by both judging and completing analogical relations based on the functional properties of objects, such as their capacity to open or to mark other objects. For example, a can opener holds the same functional relation to a can of vegetables as does a key to a padlock. Gillan et al. (1981) interpreted Sarah’s performance on both geometric and functional analogy problems as evidence of her ability to establish the higher-order analogical relationships “same” or “different” between the two sides of the analogy by first comparatively assessing the lower-order relationships within each side and then comparing them. However, as described in Oden et al. (2001), at least some of Sarah’s apparent analogical-based performances could have been achieved by less sophisticated strategies, including, for example, featural matching rules and similarity, if not identity, judgments. Oden et al. (2001) further explored the boundaries of Sarah’s analogical reasoning capacities in a series of experiments that again used simple geometric forms. In two of the four conditions of this study, Sarah had to complete partially constructed analogies from either two or three alternatives, similar to the task used by Gillan et al. (1981). In the other two conditions, Sarah had to construct analogical relations by placing geometric forms from a randomized group of four or five alternatives onto the initially empty display board. This latter task is arguably more demanding, as it required Sarah first to seek unspecified relations among the available geometric elements and then to judge the analogical equivalence of these relations. When presented with four alternatives, Sarah proceeded to arrange them into valid analogies on 76% (28/37) of those trials in which her first choices had created potential analogies. When presented with five alternatives, Sarah was required not simply to arrange four items into an analogy, but to select from among the five items those four with which an analogy could be constructed. In this condition, Sarah constructed analogies on 15 out of 72 trials (21%). This performance level was substantially lower than in the other conditions, but it was still statistically different from chance [20% (the correct four out of five items) x 33% (the percentage of patterns of the 4 items that formed an acceptable analogy) = 6.7%]. The results from the Oden et al. (2001) study not only confirmed Gillan et al.’s (1981) earlier evidence that Sarah can solve analogy problems, but they provided new evidence that she could do so spontaneously; in no case, did Sarah ever attempt to use a less efficient associative strategy as can occur with children (Alexander et al., 1989). 4.5. Broader Primate Categorical Analogy Perspectives Until recently, we did not know whether the ‘profound disparity’ (Premack, 1978, 1983; Thompson & Oden, 1996) in categorical analogical problem solving between humans and chimpanzees (Hominoidea), on the one hand, and old-world monkeys (Cercopithecoidea), on the other, could be generalized to include categorical relations other than the 2-item relations of identity and nonidentity (eg., AA = BB and CD=EF but AA ≠ EF) or to new-world monkeys (Ceboidea), such as capuchins (Cebus sp.). If capuchins, like old-world monkeys were found to be handicapped with respect to their categorical analogical matching abilities this would suggest that analogical reasoning is a derived cognitive characteristic in the Hominoidea (apes and humans). Results from studies with baboons and capuchin monkeys on a categorical above/below spatial matching task by, respectively, Dépy, Fagot, and Vauclair (1999) and Spinozzi, Lubrano, and Truppa (2004) suggest that unqualified acceptance of this hypothesis may well be premature. In these studies baboons (Papio papio) (Dépy et al., 1999) and tufted capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella) (Spinozzi et al., 2004) matched pairs of “bar and dot” stimuli on the basis of the relative above and below location of the two constituent elements. For example, if the sample consisted of a dot above the horizontal bar, then the correct matching alternative likewise involved a dot above a horizontal bar and the incorrect alternative involved a dot below a horizontal bar. Conversely, the dot below the bar was correct if the sample consisted of a dot below a horizontal bar. After acquiring the initial above/below discrimination, the baboons and capuchins transferred their performances to stimuli in which the distances between the bar and dot in the response alternatives differed from that of the sample and in which the absolute spatial location of the matching and nonmatching stimuli varied on the stimulus display board. Further evidence of the conceptual ability of the capuchins on this task was inferred from the transfer of their matching performances to problems in which the shape of either the located object (i.e., the dot) or the reference object (i.e., the bar) was changed. For example, if the sample located object was a star, then a triangle was the locator in the correct alternative. Likewise, if the reference object in the sample was a horizontal bar, then it was a vertical column in the correct alternative (Spinozzi et al., 2004). These results from the relational spatial matching task are interesting on several counts. The transfer results in particular provide perhaps the first instance of relational matching by monkeys in a task in which the sample and alternative exemplars comprised only two items, as is the case in the analogical same/different matching of nonspatial identity and nonidentity by symbol sophisticated chimpanzees. There are, however, important differences in the two types of relational matching tasks. First, the nature of the spatial task mandates that at least one of the two physical features (locator or reference object) instantiating the spatial relation remains invariant across the sample and both the correct and incorrect response alternatives; in 2-item analogical same/different matching, there are no physical similarities between any of the items instantiating the relations of identity and nonidentity. Second, a continuous perceptual dimension is present in those transfer cases where the physical distance between the locator and reference objects are manipulated. The factors noted above may well have critical environmental scaffolding effects on the acquisition of the relational spatial matching task by the baboon and capuchin monkeys. Perhaps, for example, the unavoidable partial physical invariance across the sample and both alternative exemplars helps to focus an animal’s attention away from physical cues per se and toward the dimensional relational cues, thereby reducing the computational search space as suggested by Clark and Thornton (1997). If so, then one might wonder whether the categorical relational matching performance of the monkeys would transfer to other relations including the judgment of pairwise identity and nonidentity as observed in symbol sophisticated chimpanzees and most humans. At the very least, the results of Spinozzi et al. (2004), when considered together with those of Wasserman and his colleagues for pigeons and baboons, suggest a greater degree of behavioral continuity in the evolution of relational concepts – and perhaps process too – than might be suspected from an anthropocentric focus on the Hominoidea (apes and humans) alone. 4.6. Summary When it comes to relations between relations in the form of analogies, there appear to be differences among species. Pigeons and monkeys can learn to select a display containing a set of several identical icons when the sample set contains a different set of identical icons and to select a display containing a set of all different icons when the sample set contains a different set of all different icons; however, evidence of the use of an analogy when the sets of stimuli are reduced to only pairs of identical or nonidentical items appears to occur reliably in only apes (especially one ape, Sarah) and children. The failure of monkeys and pigeons to succeed at this task when the minimal number of stimuli is used may be attributed to the inability of these animals to acquire symbolic referential meaning for categorical relations of identity and nonidentity. Their greater dependence on the entropy of the various displays may also play a role. However, evidence that monkeys can acquire a generalized ‘above’ or ‘below’ spatial analogy matching task involving displays of only two constituent elements (e.g., a dot and a horizontal line) suggests that monkeys may be able to acquire rudimentary versions of two-stimulus analogies. 5. Conclusions
Animals have evolved various behavioral capacities that, when studied under the appropriate conditions, rival or even exceed those of humans. No one would question the sense of smell of the bloodhound or the strength of an elephant. And, no one would argue that humans are inherently better at navigation than pigeons or migrating birds. Often, however, we assume that our conceptual ability is not only better than that of other animals, but that it is unique to our own species. Yet, other species have undoubtedly had to overcome environmental problems that required the deployment of an assortment of cognitive processes; if asked in the appropriate way, then these animals too can provide convincing evidence of their conceptual abilities. In the present article, we have tried to present some of the evidence for the learning of perceptual, associative, and relational concepts by animals. We cannot say that nonhuman animals have cognitive capacities that are equivalent to those of adult humans; but, we do believe that there is now good evidence that many species of animals are likely to have some of the same conceptual abilities that have typically been reserved exclusively for humans. Why should scientists who focus on human concept learning care about these research efforts? In the first place, a truly inclusive science of cognition should center on the processes and functions of perceiving, learning, thinking, reasoning, planning, remembering, and acting, regardless of the systems performing those operations. To be sure, a strong culture of comparing a carbon-based system (human beings) with a silicon-based system (digital computers) is now well established. But, does it not make equally good, if not better, sense to compare humans to a variety of other carbon-based systems represented by living animal species that vary with respect to not only their historical and situational (phylogenetic and ecological) relatedness, but also their diverse neural organizations within and between taxa (Dehaene, Duhamel, Hauser & Rizzolatti, 2005; Emery, 2006; Morino, 2004)? The evolution of intelligence is the key organizing idea of comparative cognition, whose importance to cognitive science cannot be overstated. Common behavioral competencies may mean common origins – either by virtue of homology (shared ancestry) or homoplasy (convergent and parallel evolution) – and common origins may mean common mechanisms. Thus, research in comparative cognition importantly informs the work of those interested in both the evolution and physiological/neural underpinnings of cognition. We hope that these thoughts and this review of current research in the comparative cognition of conceptualization will deepen our understanding of the design and function of intelligent systems. If we are ever to fully understand the human mind, then knowing how it is similar to and different from other animal minds will be indispensable. References Adams, B. J., Fields, L., & Verhave, T. (1993). Formation of generalized equivalence classes. Psychological Record, 43, 553-566. Alexander, P. A., Wilson, V. L., White, C. S., Fuqua, J. D., Clark, G. D., Wilson, A. F., & Kulikowich, J. M. (1989). Development of analogical reasoning in 4- and 5-year-old children. Cognitive Development, 4, 65-88. Anderson, J. R. (1991). The adaptive nature of human categorization. Psychological Review, 98, 409-429. Astley, S. L., & Wasserman, E. A. (1992). Categorical discrimination and generalization in pigeons: All negative stimuli are not created equal. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 18, 193-207. Aust, U., & Huber, L. (2002). Target-defining features in a “people-present/people-absent” discrimination task by pigeons. Animal Learning & Behavior, 30, 165-176. Bekoff, M., Allen, C., & Burghardt, G. M. (2002). The cognitive animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bhatt, R. S. (1988). Categorization in pigeons: Effects of category size, congruity with human categories, selective attention, and secondary generalization. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Iowa, Iowa City. Bhatt, R. S., Wasserman, E. A., Reynolds, W. F., Jr., & Knauss, K. S. (1988). Conceptual behavior in pigeons: Categorization of both familiar and novel examples from four classes of natural and artificial stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 14, 219-234. Blaisdell, A. P., & Cook, R. G. (2005). Two-item same-different concept leaning in pigeons. Learning & Behavior, 33, 67-77. Bovet, D., & Vauclair, J. (1998). Functional categorization of objects and their pictures in baboons (Papio anubis). Learning & Motivation, 29, 309-322. Bovet, D., & Vauclair, J. (2001). Judgment of conceptual identity in monkeys. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 8, 470-475. Boysen, S. T. (1993). Counting in chimpanzees: Nonhuman principles and emergent properties of number. In S. T. Boysen, & E. J. Capaldi, (Eds.), The development of numerical competency: Animal and human models. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Associates. Boysen, S. T., & Berntson, G. G. (1989). Numerical competence in a chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 103, 23-31. Boysen, S. T., Berntson G. G., Shreyer, T. A., & Quigley, K. S. (1993). Processing of ordinality and transitivity by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 107, 208-215. Bryant, P. E., & Trabasso, T. (1971). Transitive inference and memory in young children. Nature, 232, 456-458. Carey, S. (1978). The child as word learner. In M. Halle, G. Miller, & J. Bresnan (Eds.), Linguistic theory and psychological reality (pp. 264-293) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chater, N. & Heyes, C. (1994). Animal concepts: Content and discontent. Mind & Language, 9, 210-246. Clark, A., & Thornton, C. (1997). Trading spaces: Computation, representation, and the limits of uniformed learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 57-90. Clement, T. S., & Zentall, T. R. (2003). Choice based on exclusion in pigeons. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 10, 959-964. Colwill, R. M. (1984). Disruption of short-term memory for reinforcement by ambient illumination. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36B, 235-258. Cook, R. G. (Ed). (2001). Avian visual cognition. Retrieved from http://www.comparativecognition.org/. Cook, R. G., & Wasserman, E. A. (2006). Relational learning in pigeons. In E. A. Wasserman, & T. R. Zentall (Eds.), Comparative cognition: Experimental explorations of animal intelligence (pp. 307-324). London: Oxford University Press. Cook, R. G., & Wasserman, E. A. (in press). Learning and transfer of relational matching-to-sample by pigeons. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. Cook, R. G., Wright, A. A., & Kendrick, D. F. (1990). Visual categorization by pigeons. In M. L. Commons, R. J. Herrnstein, S. M. Kosslyn, & D. M. Mumford (Eds.), Quantitative analyses of behavior: Pattern recognition, Vol. VIII (pp. 187-214). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Couvillon, P. A., & Bitterman, M. E. (1992). A conventional conditioning analysis of “transitive inference” in animals. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 18, 308-310. Cummins, D., & Allen, C. (1998). The Evolution of Mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Davis, H. (1992). Transitive inference in rats (Rattus norvegicus). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 106, 342-349. Dehaene, S., Duhamel, J. R., Hauser, M. D., & Rizzolatti, G. (Eds.). (2005). From monkey brain to human brain: A Fyssen foundation symposium. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Delamater, A. R., & Joseph, P. (2000). Common coding in symbolic matching tasks with humans: Training with a common consequence or antecedent. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology B: Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 53B, 255-274. Delius, J. D. (1994). Comparative cognition of identity. In International perspectives on psychological science, Vol. 1: Leading themes (pp. 25-40). Bertelson, P & Eelen, P. (Eds.). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Dépy, D., Fagot, J., & Vauclair, J. (1999). Processing of above/below categorical spatial relations by baboons (Papio papio). Behavioural Processes 48, 1-9. De Rose, J. C. (1996). Controlling factors in conditional discrimination and tests of equivalence. In T. R. Zentall & P. M. Smeets (Eds.), Stimulus class formation in humans and animals (pp. 253-278). Amsterdam: Elsevier. Dixon, L. S. (1977). The nature of control by spoken words over visual stimulus selection. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 27, 433-442. Edwards, C. A., & Honig, W. K. (1987). Memorization and “feature selection” in the acquisition of natural concepts in pigeons. Learning and Motivation, 18, 235-260. Emery, N. J. (2006). Cognitive ornithology: The evolution of avian intelligence. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B., 361, 23-43. Fagot, J. (1999). Picture perception in animals. Cahiers de Psychologie Cognitive/Current Psychology of Cognition, 18, 5-6. Fagot, J., Wasserman, E. A., & Young, M. E. (2001). Discriminating the relation between relations: The role of entropy in abstract conceptualization by baboons (Papio papio) and humans (Homo sapiens). Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 27, 316-328. Farthing, G. W., Wagner, J. W. Gilmour, S., & Waxman, H. M. (1977). Short-term memory and information processing in pigeons. Learning and Motivation, 8, 520-532. Fersen, L. v., Wynne, C. D. L., Delius, J. D., & Staddon, J. E. R. (1991). Transitive inference formation in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 17, 334-341. Fetterman, J.G. (1996). Dimensions of stimulus complexity. Journal of Experimental Psychology:Animal Behavior Processes, 22, 3-18. 17, 334-341. Flemming, T. M., Beran, M. J., & Washburn, D. A. (March, 2005). Same vs. different or uniformity vs. chaos? Perception of abstract relations by Rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta). Proceedings of the International Conference on Comparative Cognition, Melbourne, FL. Flemming, T. M., Beran, M. J., & Washburn, D. A. (2007). Disconnect in concept learning by Rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta): Judgment of relations and relations-between-relations. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 33, 55-63. Frank, A. J., & Wasserman, E. A. (2005). Associative symmetry in the pigeon after successive matching-to-sample training. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 84, 147-165. French, R. M. (1995). The subtlety of sameness. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Fujita, K. (1987). Species recognition by five macaque monkeys. Primates, 28, 353-366. Fujita, K., & Matsuzawa, T. (1986). A new procedure to study the perceptual world of animals with sensory reinforcement: Recognition of humans by a chimpanzee. Primates, 27, 283-291. Gentner, D. (1998). Analogy. In W. Bechtel, & G. Graham (Eds.), A companion to cognitive science (Blackwell companions to philosophy; 13) (pp. 107-113). Malden, MA: Blackwell. Gentner, D., Holyoak, K. J., & Kokinov, B. N. (2001). The analogical mind: Perspectives from cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gillan, D. J. (1981). Reasoning in chimpanzees: II. Transitive inference. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 7, 150-164. Gillan, D. D., Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1981). Reasoning in the chimpanzee: I. Analogical reasoning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 7, 1-17. Gomez, J. C. (2004). Apes, monkeys, children, and the growth of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Grant, D. S. (1991). Symmetrical and asymmetrical coding of food and no-food samples in delayed matching in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 17, 186-193. Gray, L. (1966). Backward association in pigeons. Psychonomic Science, 4, 333-334. Grosenick, L., Clement, T. S., & Fernald, R. D. (2007) Are fish logical? Bystanders infer social rank by observation alone. Nature, 445, 429-432. Halford, G. S. (1992). Analogical reasoning and conceptual complexity in cognitive development. Human Development, 35, 193-217. Hampton, J. A. (1999). Concepts. In MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. R.A. Wilson, & F.C. Keil (Eds.), Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press (Bradford). pp 176-179. Harnad, S. (Ed.). (1987). Categorical perception: The groundwork of cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Herrnstein, R. J. (1985). Riddles of natural categorization. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B308, 129-144. Herrnstein, R. J., & de Villiers, P. A. (1980). Fish as a natural category for people and pigeons. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), Psychology of learning and motivation (pp. 59-95). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Herrnstein, R. J., & Loveland, D. H. (1964). Complex visual concept in the pigeon. Science, 146, 549-551. Heyes, C., & Huber, L. (2000). The evolution of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hogan, D. E., & Zentall, T. R. (1977). Backward associative learning in the pigeon. American Journal of Psychology, 90, 3-15. Hogue, M.-E., Beaugrand, J. P., & Lague, P. C. (1996). Coherent use of information by hens observing their former dominants defeating or being defeated by stranger. Behavioural Processes, 38, 241-252. Holyoak, K. J. (1984). Analogical thinking and human intelligence. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.), Advances in the psychology of human intelligence (vol. 2, pp. 199-230). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Holyoak, K. J., & Thagard, P. (1997). The analogical mind. American Psychologist, 52, 35-44. Homa, D., Burruel, L., & Field, D. (1987). The changing composition of abstracted categories under manipulations of decisional change, choice difficulty, and category size. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 13, 401-412. Honig, W. K., & Thompson, R. K. R. (1982). Retrospective and prospective processing in animal working memory. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation, advances in research and theory. New York: Academic Press, 239-283. Horne, P. J., & Lowe, C. F. (1996). On the origins of naming and other symbolic behavior. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 65, 185-241. House, B. J., Brown, A. L., & Scott, M. S. (1974). Children’s discrimination learning based on identity or difference. In H. W. Reese (Ed.), Advances in child development and behavior, Vol. 9, New York: Academic Press. Huber, L. (1999). Generic perception: Open-ended categorization of natural classes. In J. Fagot (Ed.). Picture perception in animals. Cahiers de Psychologie Cognitive/Current Psychology of Cognition, 18, 219-261. Kaiser, D. H., Sherburne, L. M., Steirn, J. N., & Zentall, T. R. (1997). Perceptual learning in pigeons: Decreased ability to discriminate samples mapped onto the same comparison in many-to-one matching. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 4, 378-381. Kaminski, J., Call, J., & Fischer, J. (2004). Word learning in a domestic dog: Evidence for “fast mapping.” Science, 304, 1682-1683. Kastak, C. R., & Schusterman, R. J. (2002). Sea lions and equivalence: Expanding classes by exclusion. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 78, 449-465. Katz, J. S., & Wright, A. A. (2006). Same-different abstract-concept learning by pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 32, 80-86. Katz, J. S., Wright, A. A., & Bachevalier, J. (2002). Mechanisms of same/different abstract-concept learning by rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta). Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 28, 358-368. Kuczaj, S. A. II, & Hendry, J. L. (2003). Does language help animals think? In D. Gentner (Ed.), Language in mind: Advances in the study of language and thought, pp. 237-275. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lashley, K. S. (1929). Learning: I. Nervous mechanisms in learning. In C. Murchison (Ed.), The foundations of experimental psychology, pp. 524-563. Worcester, MA: Clark University Press. Lazareva, O. F., Smirnova, A. A., Bagozkaja, M. S., Zorina, Z. A., Rayevsky, V. V., & Wasserman, E. A. (2004). Transitive responding in hooded crows requires linearly ordered stimuli. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 82, 1-19. Lazareva, O. F., Freiburger, K. L., & Wasserman, E. A. (2004). Pigeons concurrently categorize photographs at both basic and superordinate levels. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 11, 1111-1117. Lazareva, O. F., & Wasserman, E. A. (in press). Categories and concepts in animals. In R. Menzel (Ed.), Learning and memory - A comprehensive reference. Vol. II: Behavioral approaches. Elsevier. Lazareva, O. F., & Wasserman, E. A. (2006). Effect of stimulus orderability and reinforcement history on transitive responding in pigeons. Behavioural Processes, 72, 161-172. Lazareva, O. F., Wasserman, E. A., Young, M. E. (2005). Transposition in pigeons: Reassessing Spence (1937) with multiple discrimination training. Learning and Behavior, 33, 22-46. Mackintosh, N. J. (1994). Animal Learning and cognition (Handbook of perception and cognition, No. 3) San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Marino, L. (2004). Cetacean Brain Evolution: Multiplication Generates Complexity. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 17, 1-16. Matsukawa, A., Inoue, S., & Jitsumori, M. (2004). Pigeon’s recognition of cartoons: Effect of fragmentation, scrambling, and deletion of elements. Behavioural Processes, 65, 23-34. McGonigle, B. O., & Chalmers, M. (1977). Are monkeys logical? Nature, 267, 694-696. Medin, D. L., & Smith, E. E. (1984). Concepts and concept formation. Annual Review of Psychology, 35, 113-138. Mercado, E. III., Killebrew, D. A., Pack, A. A., Macha, I. V. B., & Herman, L. M. (2000). Generalization of “same-different” classification abilities in bottlenosed dolphins. Behavioural Processes, 50, 79-94. Murphy, G. L. (2002). The big book of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press (Bradford). Oden, D. L., Thompson, R. K. R., & Premack, D. (1988). Spontaneous transfer of matching by infant chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 14, 140-145. Oden, D. L., Thompson, R. K. R., & Premack, D. (1990). Infant chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) spontaneously perceive both concrete and abstract same/different relations. Child Development, 61, 621-631. Oden, D. L., Thompson R. K. R., & Premack, D. (2001). Can an ape reason analogically? Comprehension and production of analogical problems by Sarah, a Chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes). In Gentner, D., Holyoak, K. J., & Kokinov, B. N. (Eds.), Analogy: Theory and phenomena (pp. 472-497). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pas-y-Miño, C. G., Bond, A. B., Kamil, A. C., & Balda, R. P. (2004). Pinyon jays use transitive inference to predict social dominance. Nature, 430, 778–781. Pearce, J. M. (1988). Stimulus generalization and the acquisition of categories by pigeons. In L. Weiskrantz (Ed.), Thought without language (pp. 132-155). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Pepperberg, I. M. (1987). Acquisition of the same/different concept by an African Grey parrot (Psittacus erithacus): Learning with respect to categories of color, shape, and materials. Animal Learning & Behavior, 15, 423-432. Piaget, J. (1928). Judgment and reasoning in the child. New York: Harcourt. Piaget, J., Montangero, J., & Billeter, J. (1977). La formation des correlats. In J. Piaget (Eds.), L’Abstraction reflechissante (pp. 115-129). Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Premack, D. (1976). Intelligence in ape and man. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Associates. Premack, D. (1978). On the abstractness of human concepts: Why it would be difficult to talk to a pigeon. In S. Hulse, H. Fowler, & W. K. Honig (Eds.), Cognitive processes in animal behavior (pp. 423-451). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Premack, D. (1983). The codes of man and beast. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6, 125-137. Premack, D. (1988). Minds with and without language. In L. Weiskrantz (ED.), Thought without language (pp. 46-65). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Premack, A. J., & Premack, D. (1972). Teaching language to an ape. Scientific American, 227, 92-99. Quine, W. V. (1969). Natural kinds. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel (pp. 5-23). Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel. Rattermann, M. J., & Gentner, D. (1998). The use of relational labels improves young children’s performance in a mapping task. In K. Holyoak, D. Gentner, & B. Kokinov (Eds.) Advances in analogy research: Integration of theory and data from the cognitive, computational, and neural sciences. (pp. 274-282). Sofia, Bulgaria: New Bulgarian University. Richards, R. W. (1988). The question of bidirectional associations in pigeons’ learning of conditional discrimination tasks. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 26, 577-579. Roberts, W. A., & Mazmanian, D. S. (1988). Concept learning at different levels of abstraction by pigeons, monkeys, and people. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 14, 247-260. Roberts, W. A., & Phelps, M. T. (1994). Transitive inference in rats: A test of the spatial coding hypothesis. Psychological Science, 5, 368-374. Rodewald, H. K. (1974). Symbolic matching-to-sample by pigeons. Psychological Reports, 34, 987-990. Rogers, L. J., & Kaplan, G. (Eds.) (2004). Comparative Vertebrate Cognition Are Primates Superior to Non-Primates? Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers. Roitblat, H. L., & Meyer, J.-M. (1995). Comparative approaches to cognitive science. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Sands, S. F., Lincoln, C. E., & Wright, A. A. (1982). Pictorial similarity judgments and the organization of visual memory in the rhesus monkey. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 111, 369-389. Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S. (1986). Ape language: From conditioned response to symbol. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S., Rumbaugh, D. M., Smith, S. T., & Lawson, J. (1980). Reference: The linguistic essential. Science, 210, 922-925. Schank, R. C., Collins, G. C., & Hunter, L. E. (1986). Transcending inductive category formation in learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 9, 639-651. Schrier, A. M., & Brady, P. M. (1987). Categorization of natural stimuli by monkeys (Macaca mulatta): Effects of stimulus set size and modification of exemplars. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 13, 136-143. Schusterman, R. J., & Kastak, C. R. (1993). A California sea lion (Zalophus californianus) is capable of forming equivalence relations. Psychological Record, 43, 823-839. Shannon, C. E., & Weaver, W. (1949). The mathematical theory of communications. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Shettleworth, S. J. (1998). Cognition, evolution, and behavior. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Sidman, M. (1971). Reading and auditory-visual equivalences. Journal of Speech and Hearing Research, 14, 5-13. Sidman, M. (1990). Equivalence relations: Where do they come from? In D. E. Blackman & H. Lejeune (Eds.), Behaviour analysis in theory and practice: Contributions and controversies (pp. 93-114). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Sidman, M., & Tailby, W. (1982). Conditional discrimination vs. matching-to-sample: An expansion of the testing paradigm. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 37, 5-22. Siegler, R. S., & Crowley, K. (1992). Microgenetic methods revisited. American Psychologist, 47, 1241-1243. Siemann, M., & Delius, J. D. (1998). Algebraic learning and neural network models for transitive and non-transitive responding. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 10, 307-334. Smith, E. E., & Medin, D. L. (1981). Categories and concepts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Smith, H. J., King, J. E., Witt, E. D., & Rickel, J. E. (1975). Sameness-difference matching from sample by chimpanzees. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 6, 469-471. Spence, K. W. (1937). The differential response in animals to stimuli varying within a single dimension. Psychological Review, 44, 430-444. Spinozzi, G. (1993). Development of spontaneous classificatory behavior in chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes), Journal of Comparative Psychology, 107, 193-200. Spinozzi, G., Lubrano, G., & Truppa, V. (2004). Categorization of above and below spatial relations by tufted capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 118, 403-412. Staddon, J. E. R. (1983). Adaptive behavior and learning. Preface p. xii. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Steirn, J. N., Weaver, J. E., & Zentall, T. R. (1995). Transitive inference in pigeons: Simplified procedures and a test of value transfer theory. Animal Learning & Behavior, 23, 76-82. Sternberg, R. J. (1977). Intelligence, information processing, and analogical reasoning. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Sternberg, R., & Kaufman, J. (2002). The Evolution of Intelligence. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Stromer, R., and MacKay, H. (1996). Naming and the formation of stimulus classes. In T. R. Zentall, & P. M. Smeets (Eds.), Stimulus class formation in humans and animals (pp. 221-252). Amsterdam: Elsevier. Thompson, R. K. R. (1995). Natural and relational concepts in animals. In H. Roitblat, & J. A. Meyer (Eds.), Comparative approaches to cognitive science, Cambridge, MA: Bradford, MIT Press. Thompson, R. K. R., & Oden, D. L. (1993). “Language training” and its role in the expression of tacit propositional knowledge in chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). In H. L. Roitblat, L. M. Herman, & P. E. Nachtigall (Eds.), Language and communication: Comparative perspectives, pp. 365-384. Hillsdale, N J: Erlbaum. Thompson, R. K. R., & Oden, D. L. (1996). A profound disparity revisited: Perception and judgment of abstract identity relations by chimpanzees, human infants, and monkeys. Behavioural Processes (Special Issue: Cognition & Evolution), 35, 149-161. Thompson, R. K. R., & Oden, D. L. (2000). Categorical perception and conceptual judgments by nonhuman primates: The paleological monkey and the analogical ape. Cognitive Science, 24, 363-396. (Special issue on primate cognition; Guest editor, M. Tomasello). Thompson, R. K. R., Oden, D. L., & Boysen, S. T. (1997). Language-naive chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) judge relations-between-relations in an conceptual matching task. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 23, 31-43. Thompson, R. K. R., Oden, D. L., & Washburn, D. A. (in preparation). Conditional cues for relations of identity and nonidentity fail to enable analogical matching of relations in macaque monkeys (Macaca mulatta): Conditional stimuli do not function as symbols. Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (1997). Primate Cognition. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Tyrrell, D. J., Stauffer, L. B., & Snowman, L. G. (1991). Perception of abstract identity/difference relationships by infants. Infant Behavior and Development, 14, 125-129. Tyrrell, D. J., Zingaro, M. C., & Minard, K. L. (1993). Learning and transfer of identity-difference relationships by infants. Infant Behavior and Development, 16, 43-52. Urcuioli, P. J. (1996). Acquired equivalences and mediated generalization in pigeon’s matching-to-sample. In T. R. Zentall, & P. M. Smeets (Eds.), Stimulus class formation in humans and animals (pp. 55-70). Amsterdam: North Holland. Urcuioli, P. J., Zentall, T. R., Jackson-Smith, P., & Steirn, J. N. (1989). Evidence for common coding in many-to-one matching: Retention, intertrial interference, and transfer. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 15, 264-273. Vauclair, J. (1996). Animal cognition: An introduction to modern comparative psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Vaughan, W., Jr. (1988). Formation of equivalence sets in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 14, 36-42. Vogels, R. (1999). Categorization of complex visual images by rhesus monkeys. Part 1: behavioural study. European Journal of Neuroscience, 11, 1223-1238. Vonk, J., & McDonald, S. E. (2002). Natural concepts in a juvenile gorilla (Gorilla gorilla gorilla) at three levels of abstraction. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 78, 315-332. Vonk, J., & McDonald, S. E. (2004). Levels of abstraction in orangutan (Pongo abelii) categorization. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 118, 3-13. Washburn, D. A., Thompson, R. K. R., & Oden D. L. (1997). Monkeys trained with same/different symbols do not match relations. Paper presented at the 38th Annual Meeting of the Psychonomic Society, Philadelphia, PA. Wasserman, E. A. (1995). The conceptual abilities of pigeons. American Scientist, 83, 246-255. Wasserman, E. A., & Bhatt, R. S. (1992). Conceptualization of natural and artificial stimuli by pigeons. In W. K. Honig and J. G. Fetterman (Eds.), Cognitive aspects of stimulus control (pp. 203-223). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Wasserman, E. A., DeVolder, C. L., & Coppage, D. J. (1992). Non-similarity based conceptualization in pigeons via secondary or mediated generalization. Psychological Science, 6, 374-379. Wasserman, E. A., Fagot, J., & Young, M. E. (2001). Same-different conceptualization by baboons (Papio papio): The role of entropy. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 115, 42-52. Wasserman, E. A., Hugart, J. A., & Kirkpatrick-Steger, K. (1995). Pigeons show same-different conceptualization after training with complex visual stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 21, 248-252. Wasserman, E. A., & Rovee-Collier, C. (2001). Conceptualization by infants and pigeons. In M. E. Carroll and J. B. Overmier (Eds.), Animal research and human health: Advancing human welfare through behavioral science (pp. 263-279). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Wasserman, E. A., Young, M. E., & Cook, R. G. (2004). Variability discrimination in humans and animals: Implications for adaptive action. American Psychologist, 59, 879-890. Wasserman, E. A., Young, M. E., & Fagot, J. (2001 ). Effects of number of items on the baboon’s discrimination of same from different visual displays. Animal Cognition, 4, 163-170. Wasserman, E. A., Young, M. E., & Nolan, B. C. (2000). Display variability and spatial organization as contributors to the pigeons discrimination of complex visual stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 26, 133-143. Wasserman, E. A., & Zentall, T. R. (2006). Comparative cognition: Experimental explorations of animal intelligence. London: Oxford University Press. Weaver, J. E., Dorrance, B. R., & Zentall, T. R. (1999). Present/absent sample matching in pigeons: Is comparison choice controlled by the sample stimulus or by differential sample responding? Animal Learning & Behavior, 27, 288-294. Weaver, J. E., Steirn J. N., & Zentall, T. R. (1997). Transitive inference in pigeons: Control for differential value transfer. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 4, 113-117. Wilson, B., & Boakes, R. A. (1985). A comparison of the short-term memory performance of pigeons and jackdaws. Animal Learning & Behavior, 13, 285-290. Wright, A. A., & Katz, J. S. (2006). Mechanisms of same/different concept learning in primates and avians. Behavioural Processes, 72, 234-254. Wright, A. A., Cook, R. G., Rivera, J. J., Sands, S. F., & Delius, J. D. (1988). Concept learning by pigeons: Matching-to-sample with trial unique video picture stimuli. Animal Learning & Behavior, 16, 436-444. Wright, A. A., Rivera, J. J., Katz, J. S., & Bachevalier, J. (2003). Abstract-concept learning and list-memory processing by capuchin and rhesus monkeys. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 29, 184-198. Wynne, C. D. L. (1997). Pigeon transitive inference: Tests of simple accounts of a complex performance. Behavioural Processes, 39, 95-112. Wynne, C. D. L. (2001). Animal cognition: The mental lives of animals. New York, NY: Palgrave. Yamamoto, J., & Asano, T. (1995). Stimulus equivalence in a chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes). Psychological Record, 45, 3-21. Yoshikubo, S. (1985). Species discrimination and concept formation by rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta). Primates, 26, 285-299. Young, M. E., & Wasserman, E. A. (1997). Entropy detection by pigeons: Response to mixed visual displays after same-different discrimination training. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 23, 157-170. Young, M. E., & Wasserman, E. A. (2001). Entropy and variability discrimination. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 27, 278-293. Young, M. E., & Wasserman, E. A. (2002). Detecting variety: What’s so special about uniformity? Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 131, 131-143. Young, M. E., Wasserman, E. A., & Dalrymple, R. M. (1997). Memory-based same-different conceptualization by pigeons. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 4, 552-558. Young, M. E., Wasserman, E. A., & Garner, K. L. (1997). Effects of number of items on the pigeon’s discrimination of same from different visual displays. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 23, 491-501. Zentall, T. R. (1996). An analysis of stimulus class formation in animals. In T. R. Zentall & P. M. Smeets (Eds.), Stimulus class formation in humans and animals (pp.15-34). Amsterdam: North-Holland. Zentall, T. R., Clement, T. S., & Weaver, J. E. (2003). Symmetry training in pigeons can produce functional equivalences. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 10, 387-391. Zentall, T. R., Edwards, C. A., Moore, B. S., & Hogan, D. E. (1981). Identity: The basis for both matching and oddity learning in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 7, 70-86. Zentall, T. R., Galizio, M., & Critchfield, T. S. (2002). Categorization, concept learning, and behavior analysis: An introduction. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 78, 237-248. Zentall, T. R., & Hogan, D. E. (1976). Pigeons can learning identity, difference, or both. Science, 191, 408-409. Zentall, T. R., Kaiser, D. H., Clement, T. S., Weaver, J. E., & Campbell, G. (2000). Presence/absence-sample matching by pigeons: Divergent retention functions may result from the similarity of behavior during the absence sample and the retention interval. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 26, 294-304. Zentall, T. R., Sherburne, L. M., & Urcuioli, P. J. (1995). Coding of hedonic and nonhedonic samples by pigeons in many-to-one delayed matching. Animal Learning & Behavior, 23, 189-196. Zentall, T. R., Urcuioli, P. J., Jagielo, J. A., & Jackson-Smith, P. (1989). Interaction of sample dimension and sample-comparison mapping on pigeons’ performance of delayed conditional discriminations. Animal Learning & Behavior, 17, 172-178.
TRZ’s
research was supported by grants from the National Institute of Mental Health
(MH 59194 and MH 63726) and EAW’s research was supported by grants from the
National Science Foundation (IBN 99-04569) and the National Institute of
Mental Health (MH 47313). |