The Hydra’s Tale: Imagining Disgust
by Robert Rawdon Wilson
Edmonton: U
Alberta P, 2002.
Reviewed by Aletheia Plankiw
Big publishing houses occasionally publish small, even
unmeritorious, books. What happens when a small publishing house publishes
a big, even
important, book? A reviewer’s task becomes
exceptionally difficult. The
world of scholarly reviewing is not set up easily to
receive news from small
presses. Robert Rawdon Wilson’s The Hydra’s Tale:
Imagining Disgust points
the nature of the problem. Wilson, the author of
several books on literary
theory, one on Shakespeare and collections of short
fiction, has written an
important book on the theory of disgust, the nature of
representation and
the workings of the human imagination. His publisher,
the University of
Alberta Press, must be finding it difficult, even
perplexing, to get the
news of his new book out into the world.
The Hydra’s Tale is a far-ranging discussion of a
group of important and
ever-present, actual-world phenomena: loathing,
aversions, phobias and
disgust. The discussion ranges from what happens in
the world to how
representations of filth work and achieve their effects
in art, film and
fiction. There are frequent shifts from tight
argument, and the “subtextual
dungeon of documentation” (299), to personal tales,
yarns, anecdotes and
fables. The fiction is scattered throughout the book,
some of it even
appearing in the endnotes. The endnotes are a treat in
themselves. Some of
the pleasures of Nabokov’s Pale Fire nudge the reading
experience. The
Hydra’s Tale is essentially a work of theory, but one
based on readings of
multiple texts, including film, and experience equally
diverse (imaginative,
personal and vicarious). Wilson’s study of/on the
theory of disgust is far
from being disgusting. Instead, it is informative,
entertaining, engaging,
even moving (as one might not expect from a book on
theory). It is crafted
as a textual labyrinth, designed with architectural
care, in which different
planes, shelves and trajectories cross over, and
through, one another.
There are also quite a few self-contained nooks and
niches.
Each of the book’s seven chapters and conclusion takes
a part of the
mythological Hydra’s body as a symbolic rubric. For
example, chapter 2
(“Its Stench”) treats the problem of having a theory of
disgust while
chapter 3 (“Its Lair”) considers the important, if
often ignored,
distinction between disgusting things in the world and
their representations
in art. Is there a difference between seeing, or
participating in, a golden
shower and only reading about one, or seeing one danced
in a ballet? (Or
imagining Danaë being thus inseminated?) Chapter 7
(“Its Venom”) discusses
the destructive nature of feeling abject. The rubrics
are more provocations
than road-maps. The latter do appear, in both the
introduction and the
conclusion and at other points along the route of the
discussion, as if the
author knew that his method might prove perplexing.
Although he makes
demands upon his readers (and it is refreshing to have
such demands made if,
like me, you like to dance), Wilson’s sudden changes in
pace, shifting from
the rhythms of one world of discourse to another, does
not obscure the clarity
of the argument.
Wilson argues cogently, if complexly, that disgust is
a commonplace human
affect, or reaction-formation, that seems obvious.
Something disgusts you
because it is loathsome, filthy, out of place or
otherwise anomalous (from a
personal world-view). A person realizes that the
thing she sees is
disgusting because she feels nausea, experiences
gagging and may, as a
consequence, vomit. Disgust begins in what William Ian
Miller, in his
Anatomy of Disgust (1997), calls the “fetid zone of. .
. life soup, the
roiling stuff of eating, defecation, fornication,
generation, death, rot,
and regeneration” (303, n. 3). Since, in this view,
disgust is so
self-evidently natural, its attendant theories are
correspondingly simple,
straight-forward and (as theoretical models)
streamlined. Disgust is either
a natural response to ugly facts or else a conditioned
response acquired
during your earliest social formation. In either case,
it is invariant,
subject to change only in the event of madness or
dementia. It is also
primary material for moralists. Miller, for example,
argues that disgust
underlies laws since it would be impossible to prohibit
an action if it were
not already commonly found to be disgusting. Other
moralists use “disgust”
as a weapon in ethical, religious and cultural wars.
It is a common insult
which, though empty, few receive cheerfully. Wilson
notes that George
Eliot’s Middlemarch uses “disgust” at least forty-six
times, but no one
vomits (9). It is entirely a moral judgment, coupling
a veiled insult, but
its usefulness derives from preconceptions about
in-the-world disgust and a
facile assumption that everyone, right-minded people at
least, will agree
that disgust is obvious and self-evident.
Few things are further from the case than the obvious.
Wilson unpacks a
number of theories of disgust, showing how they cast a
partial light upon
the problem while utterly failing to explain the
phenomenon. “Nothing could
be more wrong than the naïve and unexamined assumption
that disgust is a
‘natural’ response,” he writes, “but even vastly more
subtle accounts fall
short of the problem’s complexity” (295). There are
three main movements
in the argument: 1) disgust is everywhere, “roiling”
and muck-like, but it
also shifts from culture to culture, from one
historical period to another;
2) despite the rigid constructions of theory, the human
response is
metamorphic, always changing from one stage in
experience to another; 3)
disgust gestates in the imagination which responds to
the world, and all its
deliquescent sliminess, by creating momentary disgust
“scenarios.” One
objection that Wilson raises against Miller’s germinal
book is that it
ignores all art, film and literature. (He quotes an
Australian scholar who
had observed that writing a book on disgust without
mentioning modern
literature was similar to writing on mass destruction
without mentioning
anything since the Charge of the Light Brigade [406, n.
91].) Wilson’s
chapter 5 (“Its Many Eyes”) explores the theory of the
imagination, drawing
upon phenomenologists, such as Sartre and Edward Casey,
to conclude that the
imagination takes the world as an archive of “props”
out of which it
reconstructs its experience. Disgust resides in the
first place in the
imagination and only secondarily in the visceral
encounters of actual-world
disgust.
This account of the imagination underlies Wilson’s
frequent shifts from one
order of discourse to another. Fiction may not be the
traditional vehicle
for argument, but it is far and away the best for the
presentation of the
problem. Each chapter begins with an autobiographical
tale that serves to
focus the central problem of the chapter. Thus chapter
3 begins with the
memories of a dismally failed sexual encounter when the
author was nineteen.
A merchant seaman at the time, he meets an older
woman in San Francisco
who insists upon a golden shower. The experience
nauseates the author, but
it leads him in highly intricate ways into a web of
overlapping issues
involved in separating an act from its representation.
Chapter 6 ("Its
Heads”), which analyzes the “perverse geometries” the
recognition of which
inspires disgust at belief-systems and ideologies and
leads to the creation
of horror and terror scenarios (the distinction between
which, Wilson makes
splashingly clear), begins with the author’s memories
of three violent
experiences concerning broken bottles in bars. Each
chapter has its own
specific autobiographical set-up. Here is an example
from the Introduction
where the author introduces a key point that individual
disgust reactions,
always highly metamorphic, change during the course of
one’s life
experiences:
Once in the remote bush of Western Australia, I found
the ground meat that I
had intended to cook for dinner already fly-blown. It
slithered with
maggots, all performing their little humping crawl
beneath the plastic
covering. In a spasm of loathing, I threw the
contaminated bundle into the
rubbish, rushing to wash my hands as quickly as I
could. However, an
experienced bushman rescued the package and showed me
how to cook the meat
using a long-handled frying pan over an open fire. By
keeping one side of
the skillet relatively cool, slanted downwards and
hanging out over the
fire, he tricked the maggots, desperate to continue
their minimal existence,
into crawling out of the meat onto the cool side. He
then dumped them into
the fire and, presto! the meat was now ready to eat,
savoury if not entirely
appetizing. (A bit later, I learned that many bushmen
would simply cook up
the maggots in fly-blown meat, devouring the ugly dish
without qualms as
just “protein.”) For many people, such as my mother,
the taboos that govern
disgust-reactions might still operate. A numbing sense
of pollution would
still make the meat impossible to eat. The maggots in
the fly-blown meat
had vanished, but not the overpowering awareness that
they had been there.
(xii-xiii)
The story looks forward to the later discussion of
shifts in disgust
responses, the centrality of eating (and food) to the
argument, the
wide-spreading sense of pollution that follows disgust
like a personal
plague, and the deep human feeling of fragility and
openness to
contamination.
The Hydra’s Tale offers the reader fresh insights into
the phenomenon of
disgust and into the encompassing issues of theory. It
is strong on the
distinction between in-the-world disgust and
representations of disgust in
art, a far more useful distinction in my opinion than
the one between
fiction and non-fiction (a boundary that Wilson takes,
and gives, delight in
transgressing). Some writers, such as Homer,
Shakespeare, Cervantes,
Proust, Joyce and Borges, find ways to bring all of
literature into specific
moments in their texts, including the processes of
writing and reading and
the blurring of boundaries. Readers who can navigate
such cross-temporal,
cross-lingual, cross-cultural writers will not find
Wilson’s strategies
particularly strange, even though he reverses the
normal relationship in
which theory serves fiction. This reversal, and
variations upon it, are not
unheard of.
I enjoyed Wilson’s book. Since The Hydra’s Tale is
notably
cross-disciplinary, readers with a range of interests
might enjoy it for all
sorts of reasons other than aesthetic (brief histories
of techniques of
executions, and so on), but I responded primarily to
its shifts in
discursive levels and its multiple creation of passages
of ficto-theory. It
is obvious, I thought in reading, that the boundaries
between fiction and
non-fiction are easily as arbitrary and porous as
Wilson insists.
Aletheia Plankiw lives in Alberta.
|