"How to deal with secessionist demands in
democracies?"
Notes for an address
by the Honourable Stéphane Dion
President of the Privy Council and
Minister of Intergovernmental Affairs
Keynote address delivered
to members of the Constitution Unit
University College London
London, United Kingdom
October 15, 2003
Check against delivery
Secession, or the act of separating from a state to form a new one, is a
particularly rare phenomenon in democracy. In fact, there has never been a well
established democracy, having had at least ten consecutive years of genuine
universal suffrage, that has experienced secession. The cases most often
mentioned occurred only a few years after the introduction or significant
expansion of universal suffrage: Norway and Sweden in 1905, Iceland and Denmark
in 1918, Ireland and the United Kingdom in 1922. Numerous secessions have
occurred since the end of the Second World War, but they have all arisen in the
context of decolonization or during periods of transition that have marked the
passage between the end of authoritarian or totalitarian regimes and the
establishment of new democracies.
That a well established democracy has never experienced secession does not
mean such a phenomenon cannot happen. But it nevertheless suggests, as I will
show, that it is difficult to reconcile secession and democracy.
In a few democratic states, there are political parties which, in a
completely peaceful manner, by a democratic route, seek to effect secession. It
is these peaceful secessionist claims I want to address here, not those that
resort to violence and terrorism. I take it for granted we all agree that we
must not give in to terrorism. The only question I am asking is as follows: how
should a democracy react to a perfectly peaceful secessionist claim?
Such a claim exists in your country, with the Scottish National Party (SNP)
which wants to make Scotland an independent state, no longer part of the United
Kingdom.1 It also exists in my
country, Canada, with the Parti québécois and the Bloc québécois,
which want Quebec to become an independent state, no longer part of Canada. One
could also mention the case of Spain, where the political party currently in
power in the autonomous community of the Basque Country, the Basque Nationalist
Party (Partido Nacionalista Vasco, PNV), is advocating accession to
independence by peaceful means and has dissociated itself from acts of violence
by ETA. How should these democracies treat these peaceful secessionist claims?
Let us first note that in those three countries, those peaceful separatist
parties are legally recognized in every respect. They have the right to run
candidates in elections, to sit in Parliament and in Spanish Cortes if
they are so elected, and to govern if warranted. But would they have the right
to effect secession?
In Spain, the major political parties, the Popular Party (Partido Popular,
PP) and the Socialist Party (Partido Socialista Obrero Español, PSOE),
respond in the negative to a right to secession, citing the indivisibility of
the country, a character which is entrenched in article 2 of the Spanish
Constitution: “The Constitution is based on the indissoluble unity of the
Spanish nation, the common and indivisible homeland of all Spaniards, and
recognizes and guarantees the right to autonomy of the nationalities and regions
which make it up and the solidarity among all of them.” Indeed, many other
well established democracies entrench their indivisibility in their
constitution, explicitly or implicitly. These include France, the United States,
Italy, Australia and many other democracies which affirm that they form
indissoluble entities.2
In your country, the SNP has stated that if it were to form the Scottish
government, it would ask the Scots by referendum, in the course of its first
mandate (four years), if they want their independence.3
The SNP also says
that, even if that referendum was perhaps only consultative from a legal
standpoint, the United Kingdom would be politically
obliged to consent to secession if a majority of Scots supported it. Would such
an obligation really exist? In the Scottish legislative election last spring,
the validity of such a referendum appeared to be challenged, and Scots
separatist leaders were outraged.4
This question concerns only the British, just as Canadian unity concerns only
Canadians, or Spanish unity only Spaniards. Canada cherishes its faithful
relations with a strong and, indeed, united UK, but it does not interfere or
intervene in British domestic affairs.
Rather, the question that arises is whether there are universal principles
that are likely to guide democracies facing peaceful secessionist claims. In
that respect, it may be helpful if, as Canada’s Intergovernmental Affairs
Minister, charged with the responsibility for national unity for the past eight
years, I were to set out for you the major recent developments in Canada.
On June 29, 2000, Canada became the first major democratic state to
acknowledge its own divisibility through legislation. In the Act to give
effect to the requirement for clarity as set out in the opinion of the Supreme
Court of Canada in the Quebec Secession Reference, more simply called the Clarity
Act, the Canadian Parliament specified the circumstances in which the
Government of Canada might undertake negotiations on the secession of one of its
provinces. Today I would like to highlight the ethical underpinnings of that
Act, which I had the honour of sponsoring in the Canadian Parliament. I am
grateful for the opportunity given to me at such a prestigious forum as the
Constitution Unit.
The Clarity Act received broad support, but was also criticized both
by the proponents of secession on demand and by those who, on the contrary,
advocate the absolute indivisibility of the national territory. I shall begin my
presentation with a critical examination of the secession-on-demand thesis,
before describing the Clarity Act and its underlying principles.
1. The three weaknesses of the secession-on-demand thesis
For the past three decades, Quebec secessionist leaders have defended a
thesis I shall summarize as follows. According to this thesis, a mere victory in
a provincial election would allow a Parti québécois government to
effect Quebec’s independence through a majority vote in its National Assembly.
Holding a referendum would not be considered necessary in law, although it is
acknowledged that such approval from the population of Quebec would be an
additional source of democratic legitimacy. It is the Government of Quebec
which, because of its majority in its National Assembly, would formulate the
referendum question. A majority result, however slim in favour of the
government’s proposal, would be sufficient for Quebec’s National Assembly to
be able to proclaim independence. But before that proclamation of independence
took place, negotiations could be undertaken with the Government of Canada in
order to facilitate the transition and with a view to eventually forming an
economic association or political and economic partnership. Nevertheless, at any
point in those negotiations, the National Assembly could unilaterally proclaim
itself to be the parliament of an independent state. As soon as it were made,
that declaration of independence would apply to all of Quebec’s territory, the
borders of which would be sacred. All citizens and all governments would
henceforth be bound to consider the Government of Quebec to be effectively the
government of an independent state. Negotiations could continue, but now between
two independent states.
This procedure for secession is well reflected in Bill 1, An Act
Respecting the Future of Québec,5 introduced by the
Government of Quebec in the National Assembly prior to the 1995 referendum.
Under section 1, “The National Assembly is authorized, within the scope of
this Act, to proclaim the sovereignty of Québec.” For greater certainty,
section 2 specifies: “On the date fixed in the proclamation of the National
Assembly, the Declaration of sovereignty appearing in the Preamble shall take
effect and Québec shall become a sovereign country [...] .” Section 26
adds that the negotiations on a partnership treaty with Canada must be completed
within a one year deadline, during which time the National Assembly may
proclaim sovereignty at any point where it believed that the negotiations were
proving fruitless.
This was the Quebec separatist leaders’ conception of the procedure for
secession. They based it on the right of peoples to self-determination. At times
the Parti Québécois leaders asserted that this principle of
self-determination confers a right to secession recognized in international law,
at other times they made of it a democratic rule that transcends formal law.
Such a procedure for unilateral secession has three weaknesses that make it
unacceptable: it poses serious problems in terms of the law, fairness and
clarity.
This procedure has no legal basis. The Supreme Court of Canada has confirmed
that the government of a province does not have the right to proclaim itself,
unilaterally, the government of an independent state. It does not have that
right either under Canadian law or under international law.6
As you know, under
international law, peoples’ right to self-determination cannot form the
foundation of a right to external self-determination, that is to say, a right to
effect secession unilaterally, except in situations of colonization, military
occupation or serious human rights violations. Apart from such extreme cases,
the right to self-determination applies within the limits accorded to the
territorial integrity of states.7
Is it significant that this procedure has no legal basis? Absolutely. The
thesis by which accession to independence is a purely political question with no
legal dimension whatsoever, is incompatible with the elementary principles of
democracy and the rule of law. A government that itself acts in violation of the
law, while requiring its citizens to comply with its laws, exposes society to
dangers that are unacceptable in democracy. Why would citizens attached to a
country agree to have it taken from them illegally? There are countless
difficulties that would prevent a unilateral declaration of independence from
taking effect on the ground.
The law is not that easily discarded. Quebec separatist leaders, who
regularly claim that accession to independence is a purely political question,
never miss an opportunity to announce their intention to use their legal
authority to give effect to secession and proclaim in law the indivisibility of
the state thereby created. This leads us to the second problem inherent in this
procedure for secession on demand: not only is it without legal basis, it is
unfair.
Indeed, Quebec’s separatist leaders believe that secession on demand is
only valid for them. Canada’s territory is divisible, Quebec’s is not. If
populations concentrated in certain territories within Quebec asked to separate
in turn, or simply to remain a part of Canada, the Quebec secessionist leaders
feel they have the right to take measures to prevent them from doing so. This
problem is not theoretical: in the two referenda the Parti québécois
held and lost, the first in 1980 and the second in 1995, Aboriginal nations held
their own referenda, which clearly demonstrated their desire to remain a part of
Canada.
Finally, the third problem is that this procedure lacks clarity. It assumes
that secession can be snatched from the jaws of defeat, on the basis of an
uncertain and fragile majority which might not have been possible to obtain the
day before or the day after. A clear procedure should require that a secession
be effected on the basis of a clear majority, for it is a serious and likely
irreversible act which is binding on future generations and entails major
consequences for all citizens of the country thus divided.
The referendum question must also be clear. It is obvious that only a
question truly about secession can determine whether citizens want secession.
The Parti québécois government, in both the 1980 and 1995 referenda,
preferred to ask Quebecers a referendum question that intermingled a proposal
for independence with the maintenance of some sort of possible association with
Canada. Thus, the 1995 question read as follows: “Do you agree that Quebec
should become sovereign after having made a formal offer to Canada for a new
economic and political partnership within the scope of the bill respecting the
future of Quebec and of the agreement signed on June 12, 1995?”
With such wording, it is not surprising that many voters went to the polls
believing in good faith that independence was conditional on an agreement on
political and economic partnership with Canada. For example, in October 1995, a
poll indicated that only 46% of voters had understood that the question meant
that Quebec would become independent even if the negotiations on political and
economic partnership were to fail.8
2. Under what circumstances should negotiations on secession take place in a democracy?
So secession on demand as proposed by Quebec separatist leaders is
unacceptable for reasons of law, fairness and clarity. Should we therefore
consider Canada as indivisible? Some have maintained so, putting forward
arguments which, while not without validity, also have their limits.
It can certainly be agreed that citizens of a democracy are bound by a
principle of mutual loyalty. They owe one another their assistance regardless of
considerations of race, religion or regional belonging. For this reason, all
citizens are, so to speak, the owners of the country as a whole, with all its
potential for wealth and human solidarity. No group of citizens can take it upon
itself to monopolize citizenship over one portion of the national territory, or
to take away from fellow citizens, against their will, their right to full
belonging to the country in its entirety. All citizens should be able to pass on
to their children that right to belong. Ideally, such a right should never be
challenged in a democracy. That is probably why so many democracies consider
themselves to be indivisible.
Because loyalty binds all citizens together, over and above their
differences, no group of citizens within a democratic state can claim for itself
the right to secession on the pretext that its particular attributes –
language, culture or religion – qualify it as a nation or distinct people
within the state. As the Supreme Court of Canada has written regarding Quebec:
“Whatever be the correct application of the definition of people(s) in this
context, their right of self-determination cannot in the present circumstances [those
of a democratic state] be said to ground a right to unilateral secession.”9
But at the same time, one cannot rule out the possibility of circumstances
arising in a democracy that make negotiating a secession the least harmful of
forseeable solutions. That might be the case in the event that one part of the
population clearly expresses, peacefully but resolutely, its desire no longer to
be part of the country. Indeed, there are measures which a democratic state
would not even consider to hold, against its clearly expressed will, a
population concentrated in one part of its territory. In other words, secession
is not a right in democracy, but it remains a possibility to which the existing
state may agree in the face of a clearly affirmed will for separation.
That is the position the Government of Canada has defended against both the
Quebec separatist movement and the proponents of the absolute indivisibility of
the national territory. That is the position I will now outline.
The Government of Canada affirms that it could not proceed to break up the
country nor abdicate its constitutional responsibilities toward Quebecers – or
any other Canadian population – without the assurance that this is
what they clearly want. In fact, no democratic state could cease to honour its
responsibilities toward one part of its population in the absence of clear
support for secession.
The Government of Canada would not agree to undertake any negotiations on
secession except in the event that the population of a province clearly
demonstrated its will to no longer be part of Canada. This clear will to secede
should be expressed by a clear majority in support of a question clearly
pertaining to secession, rather than on some vague proposal of political
partnership.
Negotiation on secession would be undertaken within the Canadian
constitutional framework and should be guided by a genuine quest for justice for
all. For example, in the event that territorially concentrated populations
within Quebec clearly asked to remain a part of Canada, the divisibility of
Quebec’s territory would have to be contemplated with the same spirit of
openness which led to accepting the divisibility of Canada’s territory.
The Government of Canada has expressed this position on a number of
occasions, notably through the Attorney General of Canada, when he explained to
the House of Commons the reasons why he was asking the Supreme Court of Canada
whether or not the Government of Quebec has the right to effect secession
unilaterally: “The leading political figures of all the provinces and
indeed the Canadian public have long agreed that this country will not be held
together against the will of Quebecers clearly expressed.”10
The Supreme Court of Canada rendered its opinion on August 20, 1998. It
confirms that the Government of Quebec does not have the right to effect
secession unilaterally, neither under Canadian law nor under international law.
To be legal, a secession would necessitate an amendment to Canada’s
Constitution. Such an amendment would entail the negotiation of “many
issues of great complexity and difficulty,” possibly including that of
territorial boundaries.11 The obligation to
undertake such a negotiation on secession exists only in the presence of clear
support for secession, expressed through a clear majority and a clear question.
Only such clear support would give the secessionist demand sufficient democratic
legitimacy to justify the obligation of a negotiation on secession. The
Government of Quebec would still not have a right to unilaterally effect
secession even after negotiations proved fruitless in its opinion. “Under
the Constitution, secession requires that an amendment be negotiated.”12
It was in this spirit that the Government of Canada had the Act to give
effect to the requirement for clarity as set out in the opinion of the Supreme
Court of Canada in the Quebec Secession Reference adopted in the Canadian
Parliament. This Clarity Act prohibits the Government of Canada from
undertaking negotiations on the secession of a province unless the House of
Commons has determined that the referendum question clearly pertained to
secession and that a clear majority had been expressed in favour of secession.
The Clarity Act also specifies the elements that must be included in
the agenda for the negotiations: “No Minister of the Crown shall propose a
constitutional amendment to effect the secession of a province from Canada
unless the Government of Canada has addressed, in its negotiations, the terms of
secession that are relevant in the circumstances, including the division of
assets and liabilities, any changes to the borders of the province, the rights,
interests and territorial claims of the Aboriginal peoples of Canada, and the
protection of minority rights.”13
In short, because accepting secession as an automatic right is contrary to
democracy, and given that an absolute prohibition on secession can prove to be
impracticable in a democracy, I feel the Canadian approach I have just described
is a realistic one. It consists of first focussing on the need to continually
improve a country of which all citizens can be proud, a democratic and
prosperous country whose highly diversified populations develop and flourish
with their own cultures and their own institutions, while working together
toward common objectives. If, in spite of this type of entente inherent in a
federation, a population should clearly express its desire to separate, then
negotiations on secession should be undertaken legally and with a concern for
justice for all, no matter how numerous the difficulties inherent in such a
negotiation.
Conclusion
That is the Canadian approach. Its fundamental premise that secession, while
not impossible, should be negotiated only if there is a clear will to split up,
seems to me to be just and of universal application. Such a principle is often
echoed favourably in the literature on secession. For example, according to
Doctor Daryl J. Glaser, of Strathclyde University: “Existing states should
thus allow secessions to occur provided that the secessionists can demonstrate
clear and durable majority support amongst the inhabitants of the breakaway
territory; include in the breakaway state as small as practicable a number of
people who oppose its formation, whether by demonstrating the support of super
majorities in plebiscites, [and] claiming tightly drawn boundaries [...].”14
In Canada’s case, this approach has had a beneficial effect on national
unity in introducing the notion of clarity. And indeed, if there is one thing
that clearly stands out, poll after poll, it is that with a clear question,
Quebecers choose a united Canada.15 The vast majority of
Quebecers want to remain Canadian and do not want to break the ties of loyalty
that bind them to their fellow citizens in other parts of Canada. They have no
wish to be forced to choose between their Quebec identity and their Canadian
identity. They reject the exclusive definitions of the word “people” and
want to belong to both the Quebec people and the Canadian people, in this global
world where concurrent identities will more than ever be an asset for opening
oneself to others.
Despite its obviously beneficial impact on Canadian unity, I do not doubt
that the approach I have just described as realistic may appear very daring and
too liberal in the face of the internationally abhorred phenomenon of secession.
The Canadian approach rejects the use of force, of any form of violence. It
emphasizes clarity, legality and justice for all. While it may appear idealistic
to many nations, that is precisely because this approach seeks to address in an
ideal manner situations which are complex and delicate. It could contribute, in
my view, to peace and enlightened state practice.
- I also understand that the Welsh nationalist party, Plaid Cymru,
now explicitly refers to “independence” as its goal.
- Patrick J. Monahan et al., Coming to Terms with Plan B: Ten
Principles Governing Secession (Toronto: C.D. Howe Institute Commentary
83, June 1996).
- Scottish National Party, A Constitution for a Free Scotland
(Edinburgh, September 2002).
- Alex Salmond, “Labour Blunders into Dangerous Ground on a Scots
Referendum,” The Scotsman (April 22, 2003).
- Bill No 1, An Act Respecting the Future of Québec, tabled
September 7, 1995.
- Opinion by the Supreme Court of Canada on the Reference re
Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217.
- Antonio Cassese, Self-determination of peoples: a legal reappraisal
(Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995); James Crawford, State
Practice and International Law in Relation to Unilateral Secession. (Expert’s
Report submitted to the Supreme Court of Canada on February 19, 1997); see
also Opinion by the Supreme Court of Canada on Reference Re Secession of
Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217, at par. 113 to 139.
- Maurice Pinard, Confusion and Misunderstanding Surrounding the
Sovereignist Option (Brief submitted to the legislative committee of the
House of Commons studying Bill C-20, February 24, 2000).
- Opinion by the Supreme Court, at par. 125.
- Statement by the Honourable Allan Rock, Minister of Justice and
Attorney General of Canada, in the House of Commons, Hansard
(September 26, 1996), p. 4707.
- Opinion by the Supreme Court, at par. 96.
- Opinion by the Supreme Court, at par. 97.
- Clarity Act: An Act to give effect to the requirement for clarity as
set out in the opinion of the Supreme Court of Canada in the Quebec
Secession Reference [Assented to 29th June, 2000], ch. 26, par. 3(2).
- Dr. Daryl J. Glaser, “The Right to Secession: An Anti-Secessionist
Defence,” Democratic Theories and Disaffected Democracies (Paper
for the 51st Political Studies Association Conference, Manchester, United
Kingdom, April 10-12, 2001), p. 18.
- Pinard, Confusion and Misunderstanding.
|