"Unity in Clarity: The Canadian Experience"
Notes for an address
by the Honourable Stéphane Dion
President of the Privy Council and
Minister of Intergovernmental Affairs
Address delivered to members of the
Fundación para la Libertad
Bilbao, Spain
November 25, 2003
Check against delivery
I want to thank the Fundación para la Libertad for kindly inviting me
here today, to share some perspectives with you on Canada’s experience as it
relates to the unity of democratic states. Before I begin however, I want to
express my solidarity and that of all Canadians, with all of you here who oppose
any form of violence for political purposes, who were victims of violence or
whose loved ones suffered such brutality. Terrorism and political savagery must
be vigorously opposed and eliminated. Canada condemns these terrorist acts which
cause you so much harm. The perpetrators are common criminals subject to the
full force of the law. We in Canada, who take for granted this basic right to
express political views without fear for our lives, salute you for your courage
and for your determination to build a peaceful society in this part of Spain and
Europe.
Canada is all the more saddened by the political violence raging here because
Spain is dear to its heart, especially the Basque Country. After all, our
history has brought us closer together. Many of your intrepid forebears settled
in Canada after fishing cod off our coasts. Place names such as Ile aux
Basques and Port aux Basques remind Canadians of this heritage. The
future holds the promise of further cooperation between Canada and your
innovative region, on the cultural and scientific level as well as the economic
one. A number of Canadian companies are doing business here and do indeed
appreciate the dynamic Basque entrepreneurship. One can only dream of what your
region would be able to achieve – for itself, for Spain, and indeed for the
entire world – if it was freed from the awful political violence that injures
you so unfairly.
Nationalism can be a good thing, to the extent it inspires more effective
mutual assistance within a human group, in a spirit of openness to other groups.
But it becomes a harmful and potentially dangerous force when it is seen as the
only principle of political and social organization, when it provides the only
ideological grid by which life in society is perceived. It then lends itself to
religious fundamentalism which, just like exaggerated nationalism, constitutes
the greatest menace to democracy and international security.
But rather than violent nationalism, it is with peaceful nationalism that I
will deal here. More precisely, I will exclusively address peaceful secessionist
claims which, without reservation, support a democratic debate free of any
coercion. In a few democratic states, there are political parties which, in a
completely peaceful manner, by a democratic route, seek to effect secession. The
only question I ask is as follows: how should a democracy react to a perfectly
peaceful secessionist claim?
The appropriate response to this question in Spain concerns only the Spanish,
just as Canadian unity concerns only Canadians. Canada is very pleased with the
productive relations and warm friendship it maintains with a strong and united
Spain, but it does not interfere or intervene in Spanish domestic affairs.
Rather, the question that arises is whether there are universal principles that
are likely to guide democracies facing peaceful secessionist claims.
This is a question for which an answer must be found, whether one wants
secession or not. For my part, I do not want it. I want Quebec to stay in Canada
and I would like to explain why. I will then outline the circumstances of
legality and clarity under which I would deem acceptable - although still
undesirable - Quebec’s secession from Canada. I will show how those
requirements for clarity were specified in 1998 in an opinion by the Supreme
Court of Canada, to which legislation passed in 2000 by the Parliament of Canada
gave effect. I will conclude by affirming my conviction that Quebecers will
always want to remain Canadian.
1. Plural
identities
It is to help my country stay united that I accepted the invitation from the
Prime Minister of Canada, the Right Honourable Jean Chrétien, to join his
Cabinet as Intergovernmental Affairs Minister, a responsibility I have held for
eight years. As it happens, I want to be both a Quebecer and a Canadian, without
ever having to choose between those two wonderful identities.
I am convinced that the main strength and the true grandeur of Canada is its
capacity to rally different populations around common objectives. The key idea
that led me to leave academia to enter the political arena is that of plural
identities. As a Quebecer and a Canadian, I maintain that, in this era of
globalization, when one has the opportunity to have different identities, one
should accept all of them. When we have the support of fellow citizens who open
us up to other cultural characteristics, to other experiences and other assets
than our own, we should accept their help and offer ours in return. The real
choice for me is not between being a Quebecer or a Canadian. It is not between
Quebec and Canada. It is about being a Quebecer and a Canadian, rather than
being a Quebecer without Canada. Identities add to each other, they never
subtract.
I know the majority of Quebecers feel as I do. That being said, there are
some who think otherwise. They want to be Quebecers without being Canadian. They
want Quebec to separate from Canada and become an independent state. I want to
dialogue with those fellow citizens with whom I disagree, because I believe they
are deeply wrong. I am trying to convince them not to renounce the Canadian
dimension in themselves, which fully belongs to them. But as a good democrat, I
respect them and do not consider them as enemies. I believe Quebec’s secession
from Canada would be a terrible mistake, but I would be prepared to accept it
provided it were done in accordance with democracy and the rule of law. As the
Attorney General of Canada has stated: “The leading political figures of
all the provinces and indeed the Canadian public have long agreed that this
country will not be held together against the will of Quebecers clearly
expressed.”1
So the question becomes whether secession may be effected while respecting
democracy and the rule of law, and if so, how? It may be useful, from that
viewpoint, having been Canada’s Minister of Intergovernmental Affairs with
responsibilities in connection with Canadian unity for eight years, for me to
talk about some recent developments in Canada.
In fact, you may be aware of those developments. On August 20, 1998, the
Supreme Court of Canada issued an opinion in the Reference Re Secession of
Quebec. On June 29, 2000, the Parliament of Canada passed the Act to give
effect to the requirement for clarity as set out in the opinion of the Supreme
Court of Canada in the Quebec Secession Reference. I am aware these two
legal texts are known in Spain and are referred to in your national discourse.
For example, I read, in the general policy paper that the President of the
Government of the Autonomous Community of the Basque Country, the Lehendakari
Mr. Juan José Ibarretxe, presented last September 26, the following reference
to the Supreme Court of Canada’s opinion: “The decision [opinion]
by the Supreme Court of Canada, which interprets current international law,
takes into consideration the commitment not to exercise unilaterally the right
to self-determination and the explicit recognition of the obligation to open the
process of negotiation and agreement with the state.”2
[Translation]
I need to be very clear from the outset, with all respect, that the Supreme
Court of Canada has never claimed to render an opinion that would have effect
outside Canada. That opinion is legally valid only for Canada. But because, for
very understandable reasons, it is the subject of discussions in Spain, and
indeed in other democracies, allow me to set out the logic and the ethical
underpinnings of the Supreme Court of Canada’s opinion and the Clarity Act
which gives effect thereto.
2. The
Supreme Court of Canada’s opinion on Quebec secession
Your country considers itself to be indivisible, a characteristic entrenched
in Article 2 of your Constitution: “The Constitution is based on the
indissoluble unity of the Spanish nation, the common and indivisible homeland of
all Spaniards, and recognizes and guarantees the right to autonomy of the
nationalities and regions which make it up and the solidarity among all of them.”
Indeed, many other well established democracies declare themselves indivisible
in their constitutions, explicitly or implicitly. These include France, the
United States, Italy, Australia and many other democracies which affirm that
they form indissoluble entities.
The underlying principle of that indivisibility is easily understood. That
very principle is evoked in Article 2 of your Constitution: solidarity, which
binds together all citizens and all regions of a country. One can certainly
agree that citizens of a democracy are bound by a principle of solidarity or of
mutual loyalty. They all owe one another their assistance regardless of
considerations of race, religion or regional belonging. For this reason, all
citizens are, so to speak, the owners of the country as a whole, with all its
potential for wealth and human solidarity. No group of citizens can take it upon
itself to monopolize citizenship over one portion of the national territory, or
to take away from fellow citizens, against their will, their right to full
belonging to the country in its entirety. All citizens should be able to pass on
to their children that right to belong. Ideally, such a right should never be
challenged in a democracy. That is probably why so many democracies consider
themselves to be indivisible.
Because loyalty binds all citizens together, over and above their
differences, no group of citizens within a democratic state can claim for itself
the right to secession on the pretext that its particular attributes –
language, culture or religion – qualify it as a nation or distinct people
within the state. As the Supreme Court of Canada has written regarding Quebec in
its Reference Re the Secession of Quebec of August 20, 1998: “Whatever
be the correct application of the definition of people(s) in this context, their
right of self-determination cannot in the present circumstances [those of a
democratic state] be said to ground a right to unilateral secession.”3
But at the same time, one cannot rule out the possibility of circumstances
arising in a democracy that make negotiating a secession the least harmful of
foreseeable solutions. That might be the case in the event that one part of the
population clearly expresses, peacefully but resolutely, its desire no longer to
be part of the country. There are, in fact, measures which a democratic state
would not contemplate using to hold a population, concentrated in one part of
its territory, against its clearly expressed will.
In other words, secession is not a right in democracy, but it remains a
possibility to which the existing state may agree in the face of a clearly
affirmed will for separation.
That is the position the Supreme Court of Canada took in its opinion of
August 20, 1998. It confirmed that the Government of Quebec does not have the
right to effect secession unilaterally. It does not have the right to proclaim
itself, unilaterally, the government of an independent state. It does not have
that right either under Canadian law or under international law.4
As you know, under
international law, peoples’ right to self-determination cannot form the
foundation of a right to external self-determination, that is to say, a right to
effect secession unilaterally, except in situations of colonization, military
occupation or serious human rights violations. Apart from such extreme cases,
the right to self-determination applies within the limits accorded to the
territorial integrity of states.5
The Supreme Court has confirmed that, to be legal in Canada, a secession
would necessitate an amendment to Canada’s Constitution. Such an amendment
would entail the negotiation of “many issues of great complexity and
difficulty,” perhaps including that of territorial boundaries.6
The obligation to undertake such a negotiation on secession would exist only
in the presence of clear support for secession, expressed through a clear
majority and in response to a clear question. Only such clear support would give
the secessionist demand sufficient democratic legitimacy to justify the
obligation of a negotiation on secession. The Government of Quebec would still
not have a right to unilaterally effect secession even after negotiations proved
fruitless in its opinion. “Under the Constitution, secession requires that
an amendment be negotiated.”7
3. The
Clarity Act
The Parliament of Canada passed, on June 29, 2000, the Act to give effect
to the requirement for clarity as set out in the opinion of the Supreme Court of
Canada in the Quebec Secession Reference. This law, more generally referred
to as the Clarity Act, which I had the honour of sponsoring in the
Canadian Parliament, made Canada the first major democratic state to acknowledge
its divisibility by a legal enactment. It sets out the circumstances in which
the Government of Canada could undertake negotiations on the secession of a
province. It prohibits the Government of Canada from undertaking such
negotiations unless the House of Commons has determined that the referendum
question clearly pertained to secession and that a clear majority had been
expressed in favour of secession.
The Government of Canada affirms that it could not proceed to break up the
country nor abdicate its constitutional responsibilities toward Quebecers – or
the population of any other Canadian province – without the assurance that
this is what they clearly want. In fact, no democratic state could cease to
honour its responsibilities toward one part of its population in the absence of
clear support for secession.
The Government of Canada would not agree to undertake any negotiations on
secession except in the event that the population of a province clearly
demonstrated its will to no longer be part of Canada. This clear will to secede
should be expressed by a clear majority in support of a question clearly
pertaining to secession, rather than on some vague proposal of political
partnership. If undertaking negotiations on secession is excluded, unless it is
supported by a clear majority and not an uncertain and fragile one, it is
because secession is a serious and likely irreversible act which binds future
generations and has major consequences for all citizens of the country thus
divided. The referendum question must also be clear, for it is obvious that only
a question truly about secession can determine whether citizens want secession.
Negotiation on secession should be undertaken within the Canadian
constitutional framework and should be guided by a genuine quest for justice for
all. For example, in the event that territorially concentrated populations
within Quebec clearly asked to remain a part of Canada, the divisibility of
Quebec’s territory would have to be contemplated with the same spirit of
openness which led to accepting the divisibility of Canada’s territory.
The Clarity Act also specifies the elements that must be included on
the agenda for the negotiations: “No Minister of the Crown shall propose a
constitutional amendment to effect the secession of a province from Canada
unless the Government of Canada has addressed, in its negotiations, the terms of
secession that are relevant in the circumstances, including the division of
assets and liabilities, any changes to the borders of the province, the rights,
interests and territorial claims of the Aboriginal peoples of Canada, and the
protection of minority rights.”8
Conclusion
That is the Canadian way of contemplating secession in democracy. Its
fundamental premise is that a secession cannot be effected unilaterally in
democracy. It necessarily involves constitutional negotiations. A democratic
state could undertake such negotiations only in the presence of clear support
for secession. A democratic state could not authorize secession until after such
negotiations had been duly completed, respecting established laws and justice
for all.
All I can say is that, in Canada’s case, this exercise of clarification has
had a beneficial effect on national unity. For indeed, if there is one thing
that clearly stands out, poll after poll, it is that with a clear question,
Quebecers choose a united Canada. The vast majority of Quebecers want to remain
Canadian and do not want to break the ties of loyalty that bind them to their
fellow citizens in other parts of Canada. They have no wish to be forced to
choose between their Quebec identity and their Canadian identity. They reject
the exclusive definitions of the word “people” or “nation” and want to
belong to both the Quebec people and the Canadian people, in this global world
where concurrent identities will more than ever be an asset for opening oneself
to others.
It was José Carreras who said: “Cuanto más catalán me dejan ser, más
español me siento.”9 Just think! The more
Québécois we are, the more we feel Canadian.
- Statement by the Honourable Allan Rock, Minister of Justice and Attorney General ofCanada,
in the House of Commons, September 26, 1996, Hansard, p. 4707.
- Debate
de Politíca General : Intervención del Lehendakari, Euskadico Lehendakaria/
El Lehendakari de Euskadi, Vitoria-Gasteiz, 26 de septiembre del 2003.
- Opinion
by the Supreme Court of Canada on the Reference re Secession of Quebec,[1998]
2 S.C.R. 217, at par. 125.
- Opinion
by the Supreme Court, at par. 155.
- Antonio Cassese, Self-determination of peoples: a legal reappraisal
(Cambridge,Cambridge
University Press, 1995); James Crawford, State Practice and InternationalLaw
in Relation to Unilateral Secession. (Expert’s Report submitted to the
SupremeCourt of Canada on February 19, 1997); see also Opinion by the Supreme
Court ofCanada on Reference Re Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217,
at par. 113 to 139.
- Opinion
by the Supreme Court, at par. 96.
- Opinion
by the Supreme Court, at par. 97.
- Clarity
Act: An Act to give effect to the requirement for clarity as set out in the
opinion ofthe Supreme Court of Canada in the Quebec Secession Reference
[Assented to 29th June,2000], ch. 26, par. 3(2).
-
José
Carreras, “Cuanto más catalán me dejan ser, más español me siento,”
El Mundo(Vol. VII, number 2, August 26, 1995) available at:
http://www.el-mundo.es/papel/hemeroteca/1995/08/26/uve/
|